Chapter VI
Difficulties on Theory
Difficulties on the theory of descent with modification -- Transitions --
Absence or rarity of transitional varieties -- Transitions in habits of
life -- Diversified habits in the same species -- Species with habits
widely different from those of their allies -- Organs of extreme perfection
-- Means of transition -- Cases of difficulty -- Natura non facit saltum --
Organs of small importance -- Organs not in all cases absolutely perfect --
The law of Unity of Type and of the Conditions of Existence embraced by the
theory of Natural Selection.
Long before having arrived at this part of my work, a crowd of difficulties
will have occurred to the reader. Some of them are so grave that to this
day I can never reflect on them without being staggered; but, to the best
of my judgment, the greater number are only apparent, and those that are
real are not, I think, fatal to my theory.
These difficulties and objections may be classed under the following
heads:- Firstly, why, if species have descended from other species by
insensibly fine gradations, do we not everywhere see innumerable
transitional forms? Why is not all nature in confusion instead of the
species being, as we see them, well defined?
Secondly, is it possible that an animal having, for instance, the structure
and habits of a bat, could have been formed by the modification of some
animal with wholly different habits? Can we believe that natural selection
could produce, on the one hand, organs of trifling importance, such as the
tail of a giraffe, which serves as a fly-flapper, and, on the other hand,
organs of such wonderful structure, as the eye, of which we hardly as yet
fully understand the inimitable perfection?
Thirdly, can instincts be acquired and modified through natural selection?
What shall we say to so marvellous an instinct as that which leads the bee
to make cells, which have practically anticipated the discoveries of
profound mathematicians?
Fourthly, how can we account for species, when crossed, being sterile and
producing sterile offspring, whereas, when varieties are crossed, their
fertility is unimpaired?
The two first heads shall be here discussed--Instinct and Hybridism in
separate chapters.
On the absence or rarity of transitional varieties. -- As natural selection
acts solely by the preservation of profitable modifications, each new form
will tend in a fully-stocked country to take the place of, and finally to
exterminate, its own less improved parent or other less-favoured forms with
which it comes into competition. Thus extinction and natural selection
will, as we have seen, go hand in hand. Hence, if we look at each species
as descended from some other unknown form, both the parent and all the
transitional varieties will generally have been exterminated by the very
process of formation and perfection of the new form.
But, as by this theory innumerable transitional forms must have existed,
why do we not find them embedded in countless numbers in the crust of the
earth? It will be much more convenient to discuss this question in the
chapter on the Imperfection of the geological record; and I will here only
state that I believe the answer mainly lies in the record being
incomparably less perfect than is generally supposed; the imperfection of
the record being chiefly due to organic beings not inhabiting profound
depths of the sea, and to their remains being embedded and preserved to a
future age only in masses of sediment sufficiently thick and extensive to
withstand an enormous amount of future degradation; and such fossiliferous
masses can be accumulated only where much sediment is deposited on the
shallow bed of the sea, whilst it slowly subsides. These contingencies
will concur only rarely, and after enormously long intervals. Whilst the
bed of the sea is stationary or is rising, or when very little sediment is
being deposited, there will be blanks in our geological history. The crust
of the earth is a vast museum; but the natural collections have been made
only at intervals of time immensely remote.
But it may be urged that when several closely-allied species inhabit the
same territory we surely ought to find at the present time many
transitional forms. Let us take a simple case: in travelling from north
to south over a continent, we generally meet at successive intervals with
closely allied or representative species, evidently filling nearly the same
place in the natural economy of the land. These representative species
often meet and interlock; and as the one becomes rarer and rarer, the other
becomes more and more frequent, till the one replaces the other. But if we
compare these species where they intermingle, they are generally as
absolutely distinct from each other in every detail of structure as are
specimens taken from the metropolis inhabited by each. By my theory these
allied species have descended from a common parent; and during the process
of modification, each has become adapted to the conditions of life of its
own region, and has supplanted and exterminated its original parent and all
the transitional varieties between its past and present states. Hence we
ought not to expect at the present time to meet with numerous transitional
varieties in each region, though they must have existed there, and may be
embedded there in a fossil condition. But in the intermediate region,
having intermediate conditions of life, why do we not now find
closely-linking intermediate varieties? This difficulty for a long time
quite confounded me. But I think it can be in large part explained.
In the first place we should be extremely cautious in inferring, because an
area is now continuous, that it has been continuous during a long period.
Geology would lead us to believe that almost every continent has been
broken up into islands even during the later tertiary periods; and in such
islands distinct species might have been separately formed without the
possibility of intermediate varieties existing in the intermediate zones.
By changes in the form of the land and of climate, marine areas now
continuous must often have existed within recent times in a far less
continuous and uniform condition than at present. But I will pass over
this way of escaping from the difficulty; for I believe that many perfectly
defined species have been formed on strictly continuous areas; though I do
not doubt that the formerly broken condition of areas now continuous has
played an important part in the formation of new species, more especially
with freely-crossing and wandering animals.
In looking at species as they are now distributed over a wide area, we
generally find them tolerably numerous over a large territory, then
becoming somewhat abruptly rarer and rarer on the confines, and finally
disappearing. Hence the neutral territory between two representative
species is generally narrow in comparison with the territory proper to
each. We see the same fact in ascending mountains, and sometimes it is
quite remarkable how abruptly, as Alph. De Candolle has observed, a common
alpine species disappears. The same fact has been noticed by Forbes in
sounding the depths of the sea with the dredge. To those who look at
climate and the physical conditions of life as the all-important elements
of distribution, these facts ought to cause surprise, as climate and height
or depth graduate away insensibly. But when we bear in mind that almost
every species, even in its metropolis, would increase immensely in numbers,
were it not for other competing species; that nearly all either prey on or
serve as prey for others; in short, that each organic being is either
directly or indirectly related in the most important manner to other
organic beings, we must see that the range of the inhabitants of any
country by no means exclusively depends on insensibly changing physical
conditions, but in large part on the presence of other species, on which it
depends, or by which it is destroyed, or with which it comes into
competition; and as these species are already defined objects (however they
may have become so), not blending one into another by insensible
gradations, the range of any one species, depending as it does on the range
of others, will tend to be sharply defined. Moreover, each species on the
confines of its range, where it exists in lessened numbers, will, during
fluctuations in the number of its enemies or of its prey, or in the
seasons, be extremely liable to utter extermination; and thus its
geographical range will come to be still more sharply defined.
If I am right in believing that allied or representative species, when
inhabiting a continuous area, are generally so distributed that each has a
wide range, with a comparatively narrow neutral territory between them, in
which they become rather suddenly rarer and rarer; then, as varieties do
not essentially differ from species, the same rule will probably apply to
both; and if we in imagination adapt a varying species to a very large
area, we shall have to adapt two varieties to two large areas, and a third
variety to a narrow intermediate zone. The intermediate variety,
consequently, will exist in lesser numbers from inhabiting a narrow and
lesser area; and practically, as far as I can make out, this rule holds
good with varieties in a state of nature. I have met with striking
instances of the rule in the case of varieties intermediate between
well-marked varieties in the genus Balanus. And it would appear from
information given me by Mr. Watson, Dr. Asa Gray, and Mr. Wollaston, that
generally when varieties intermediate between two other forms occur, they
are much rarer numerically than the forms which they connect. Now, if we
may trust these facts and inferences, and therefore conclude that varieties
linking two other varieties together have generally existed in lesser
numbers than the forms which they connect, then, I think, we can understand
why intermediate varieties should not endure for very long periods;--why as
a general rule they should be exterminated and disappear, sooner than the
forms which they originally linked together.
For any form existing in lesser numbers would, as already remarked, run a
greater chance of being exterminated than one existing in large numbers;
and in this particular case the intermediate form would be eminently liable
to the inroads of closely allied forms existing on both sides of it. But a
far more important consideration, as I believe, is that, during the process
of further modification, by which two varieties are supposed on my theory
to be converted and perfected into two distinct species, the two which
exist in larger numbers from inhabiting larger areas, will have a great
advantage over the intermediate variety, which exists in smaller numbers in
a narrow and intermediate zone. For forms existing in larger numbers will
always have a better chance, within any given period, of presenting further
favourable variations for natural selection to seize on, than will the
rarer forms which exist in lesser numbers. Hence, the more common forms,
in the race for life, will tend to beat and supplant the less common forms,
for these will be more slowly modified and improved. It is the same
principle which, as I believe, accounts for the common species in each
country, as shown in the second chapter, presenting on an average a greater
number of well-marked varieties than do the rarer species. I may
illustrate what I mean by supposing three varieties of sheep to be kept,
one adapted to an extensive mountainous region; a second to a comparatively
narrow, hilly tract; and a third to wide plains at the base; and that the
inhabitants are all trying with equal steadiness and skill to improve their
stocks by selection; the chances in this case will be strongly in favour of
the great holders on the mountains or on the plains improving their breeds
more quickly than the small holders on the intermediate narrow, hilly
tract; and consequently the improved mountain or plain breed will soon take
the place of the less improved hill breed; and thus the two breeds, which
originally existed in greater numbers, will come into close contact with
each other, without the interposition of the supplanted, intermediate
hill-variety.
To sum up, I believe that species come to be tolerably well-defined
objects, and do not at any one period present an inextricable chaos of
varying and intermediate links: firstly, because new varieties are very
slowly formed, for variation is a very slow process, and natural selection
can do nothing until favourable variations chance to occur, and until a
place in the natural polity of the country can be better filled by some
modification of some one or more of its inhabitants. And such new places
will depend on slow changes of climate, or on the occasional immigration of
new inhabitants, and, probably, in a still more important degree, on some
of the old inhabitants becoming slowly modified, with the new forms thus
produced and the old ones acting and reacting on each other. So that, in
any one region and at any one time, we ought only to see a few species
presenting slight modifications of structure in some degree permanent; and
this assuredly we do see.
Secondly, areas now continuous must often have existed within the recent
period in isolated portions, in which many forms, more especially amongst
the classes which unite for each birth and wander much, may have separately
been rendered sufficiently distinct to rank as representative species. In
this case, intermediate varieties between the several representative
species and their common parent, must formerly have existed in each broken
portion of the land, but these links will have been supplanted and
exterminated during the process of natural selection, so that they will no
longer exist in a living state.
Thirdly, when two or more varieties have been formed in different portions
of a strictly continuous area, intermediate varieties will, it is probable,
at first have been formed in the intermediate zones, but they will
generally have had a short duration. For these intermediate varieties
will, from reasons already assigned (namely from what we know of the actual
distribution of closely allied or representative species, and likewise of
acknowledged varieties), exist in the intermediate zones in lesser numbers
than the varieties which they tend to connect. From this cause alone the
intermediate varieties will be liable to accidental extermination; and
during the process of further modification through natural selection, they
will almost certainly be beaten and supplanted by the forms which they
connect; for these from existing in greater numbers will, in the aggregate,
present more variation, and thus be further improved through natural
selection and gain further advantages.
Lastly, looking not to any one time, but to all time, if my theory be true,
numberless intermediate varieties, linking most closely all the species of
the same group together, must assuredly have existed; but the very process
of natural selection constantly tends, as has been so often remarked, to
exterminate the parent forms and the intermediate links. Consequently
evidence of their former existence could be found only amongst fossil
remains, which are preserved, as we shall in a future chapter attempt to
show, in an extremely imperfect and intermittent record.
On the origin and transitions of organic beings with peculiar habits and
structure. -- It has been asked by the opponents of such views as I hold,
how, for instance, a land carnivorous animal could have been converted into
one with aquatic habits; for how could the animal in its transitional state
have subsisted? It would be easy to show that within the same group
carnivorous animals exist having every intermediate grade between truly
aquatic and strictly terrestrial habits; and as each exists by a struggle
for life, it is clear that each is well adapted in its habits to its place
in nature. Look at the Mustela vison of North America, which has webbed
feet and which resembles an otter in its fur, short legs, and form of tail;
during summer this animal dives for and preys on fish, but during the long
winter it leaves the frozen waters, and preys like other polecats on mice
and land animals. If a different case had been taken, and it had been
asked how an insectivorous quadruped could possibly have been converted
into a flying bat, the question would have been far more difficult, and I
could have given no answer. Yet I think such difficulties have very little
weight.
Here, as on other occasions, I lie under a heavy disadvantage, for out of
the many striking cases which I have collected, I can give only one or two
instances of transitional habits and structures in closely allied species
of the same genus; and of diversified habits, either constant or
occasional, in the same species. And it seems to me that nothing less than
a long list of such cases is sufficient to lessen the difficulty in any
particular case like that of the bat.
Look at the family of squirrels; here we have the finest gradation from
animals with their tails only slightly flattened, and from others, as Sir
J. Richardson has remarked, with the posterior part of their bodies rather
wide and with the skin on their flanks rather full, to the so-called flying
squirrels; and flying squirrels have their limbs and even the base of the
tail united by a broad expanse of skin, which serves as a parachute and
allows them to glide through the air to an astonishing distance from tree
to tree. We cannot doubt that each structure is of use to each kind of
squirrel in its own country, by enabling it to escape birds or beasts of
prey, or to collect food more quickly, or, as there is reason to believe,
by lessening the danger from occasional falls. But it does not follow from
this fact that the structure of each squirrel is the best that it is
possible to conceive under all natural conditions. Let the climate and
vegetation change, let other competing rodents or new beasts of prey
immigrate, or old ones become modified, and all analogy would lead us to
believe that some at least of the squirrels would decrease in numbers or
become exterminated, unless they also became modified and improved in
structure in a corresponding manner. Therefore, I can see no difficulty,
more especially under changing conditions of life, in the continued
preservation of individuals with fuller and fuller flank-membranes, each
modification being useful, each being propagated, until by the accumulated
effects of this process of natural selection, a perfect so-called flying
squirrel was produced.
Now look at the Galeopithecus or flying lemur, which formerly was falsely
ranked amongst bats. It has an extremely wide flank-membrane, stretching
from the corners of the jaw to the tail, and including the limbs and the
elongated fingers: the flank membrane is, also, furnished with an extensor
muscle. Although no graduated links of structure, fitted for gliding
through the air, now connect the Galeopithecus with the other Lemuridae,
yet I can see no difficulty in supposing that such links formerly existed,
and that each had been formed by the same steps as in the case of the less
perfectly gliding squirrels; and that each grade of structure had been
useful to its possessor. Nor can I see any insuperable difficulty in
further believing it possible that the membrane-connected fingers and
fore-arm of the Galeopithecus might be greatly lengthened by natural
selection; and this, as far as the organs of flight are concerned, would
convert it into a bat. In bats which have the wing-membrane extended from
the top of the shoulder to the tail, including the hind-legs, we perhaps
see traces of an apparatus originally constructed for gliding through the
air rather than for flight.
If about a dozen genera of birds had become extinct or were unknown, who
would have ventured to have surmised that birds might have existed which
used their wings solely as flappers, like the logger-headed duck
(Micropterus of Eyton); as fins in the water and front legs on the land,
like the penguin; as sails, like the ostrich; and functionally for no
purpose, like the Apteryx. Yet the structure of each of these birds is
good for it, under the conditions of life to which it is exposed, for each
has to live by a struggle; but it is not necessarily the best possible
under all possible conditions. It must not be inferred from these remarks
that any of the grades of wing-structure here alluded to, which perhaps may
all have resulted from disuse, indicate the natural steps by which birds
have acquired their perfect power of flight; but they serve, at least, to
show what diversified means of transition are possible.
Seeing that a few members of such water-breathing classes as the Crustacea
and Mollusca are adapted to live on the land, and seeing that we have
flying birds and mammals, flying insects of the most diversified types, and
formerly had flying reptiles, it is conceivable that flying-fish, which now
glide far through the air, slightly rising and turning by the aid of their
fluttering fins, might have been modified into perfectly winged animals.
If this had been effected, who would have ever imagined that in an early
transitional state they had been inhabitants of the open ocean, and had
used their incipient organs of flight exclusively, as far as we know, to
escape being devoured by other fish?
When we see any structure highly perfected for any particular habit, as the
wings of a bird for flight, we should bear in mind that animals displaying
early transitional grades of the structure will seldom continue to exist to
the present day, for they will have been supplanted by the very process of
perfection through natural selection. Furthermore, we may conclude that
transitional grades between structures fitted for very different habits of
life will rarely have been developed at an early period in great numbers
and under many subordinate forms. Thus, to return to our imaginary
illustration of the flying-fish, it does not seem probable that fishes
capable of true flight would have been developed under many subordinate
forms, for taking prey of many kinds in many ways, on the land and in the
water, until their organs of flight had come to a high stage of perfection,
so as to have given them a decided advantage over other animals in the
battle for life. Hence the chance of discovering species with transitional
grades of structure in a fossil condition will always be less, from their
having existed in lesser numbers, than in the case of species with fully
developed structures.
I will now give two or three instances of diversified and of changed habits
in the individuals of the same species. When either case occurs, it would
be easy for natural selection to fit the animal, by some modification of
its structure, for its changed habits, or exclusively for one of its
several different habits. But it is difficult to tell, and immaterial for
us, whether habits generally change first and structure afterwards; or
whether slight modifications of structure lead to changed habits; both
probably often change almost simultaneously. Of cases of changed habits it
will suffice merely to allude to that of the many British insects which now
feed on exotic plants, or exclusively on artificial substances. Of
diversified habits innumerable instances could be given: I have often
watched a tyrant flycatcher (Saurophagus sulphuratus) in South America,
hovering over one spot and then proceeding to another, like a kestrel, and
at other times standing stationary on the margin of water, and then dashing
like a kingfisher at a fish. In our own country the larger titmouse (Parus
major) may be seen climbing branches, almost like a creeper; it often, like
a shrike, kills small birds by blows on the head; and I have many times
seen and heard it hammering the seeds of the yew on a branch, and thus
breaking them like a nuthatch. In North America the black bear was seen by
Hearne swimming for hours with widely open mouth, thus catching, like a
whale, insects in the water. Even in so extreme a case as this, if the
supply of insects were constant, and if better adapted competitors did not
already exist in the country, I can see no difficulty in a race of bears
being rendered, by natural selection, more and more aquatic in their
structure and habits, with larger and larger mouths, till a creature was
produced as monstrous as a whale.
As we sometimes see individuals of a species following habits widely
different from those both of their own species and of the other species of
the same genus, we might expect, on my theory, that such individuals would
occasionally have given rise to new species, having anomalous habits, and
with their structure either slightly or considerably modified from that of
their proper type. And such instances do occur in nature. Can a more
striking instance of adaptation be given than that of a woodpecker for
climbing trees and for seizing insects in the chinks of the bark? Yet in
North America there are woodpeckers which feed largely on fruit, and others
with elongated wings which chase insects on the wing; and on the plains of
La Plata, where not a tree grows, there is a woodpecker, which in every
essential part of its organisation, even in its colouring, in the harsh
tone of its voice, and undulatory flight, told me plainly of its close
blood-relationship to our common species; yet it is a woodpecker which
never climbs a tree!
Petrels are the most aerial and oceanic of birds, yet in the quiet Sounds
of Tierra del Fuego, the Puffinuria berardi, in its general habits, in its
astonishing power of diving, its manner of swimming, and of flying when
unwillingly it takes flight, would be mistaken by any one for an auk or
grebe; nevertheless, it is essentially a petrel, but with many parts of its
organisation profoundly modified. On the other hand, the acutest observer
by examining the dead body of the water-ouzel would never have suspected
its sub-aquatic habits; yet this anomalous member of the strictly
terrestrial thrush family wholly subsists by diving,--grasping the stones
with its feet and using its wings under water.
He who believes that each being has been created as we now see it, must
occasionally have felt surprise when he has met with an animal having
habits and structure not at all in agreement. What can be plainer than
that the webbed feet of ducks and geese are formed for swimming? yet there
are upland geese with webbed feet which rarely or never go near the water;
and no one except Audubon has seen the frigate-bird, which has all its four
toes webbed, alight on the surface of the sea. On the other hand, grebes
and coots are eminently aquatic, although their toes are only bordered by
membrane. What seems plainer than that the long toes of grallatores are
formed for walking over swamps and floating plants, yet the water-hen is
nearly as aquatic as the coot; and the landrail nearly as terrestrial as
the quail or partridge. In such cases, and many others could be given,
habits have changed without a corresponding change of structure. The
webbed feet of the upland goose may be said to have become rudimentary in
function, though not in structure. In the frigate-bird, the deeply-scooped
membrane between the toes shows that structure has begun to change.
He who believes in separate and innumerable acts of creation will say, that
in these cases it has pleased the Creator to cause a being of one type to
take the place of one of another type; but this seems to me only restating
the fact in dignified language. He who believes in the struggle for
existence and in the principle of natural selection, will acknowledge that
every organic being is constantly endeavouring to increase in numbers; and
that if any one being vary ever so little, either in habits or structure,
and thus gain an advantage over some other inhabitant of the country, it
will seize on the place of that inhabitant, however different it may be
from its own place. Hence it will cause him no surprise that there should
be geese and frigate-birds with webbed feet, either living on the dry land
or most rarely alighting on the water; that there should be long-toed
corncrakes living in meadows instead of in swamps; that there should be
woodpeckers where not a tree grows; that there should be diving thrushes,
and petrels with the habits of auks.
Organs of extreme perfection and complication. -- To suppose that the eye,
with all its inimitable contrivances for adjusting the focus to different
distances, for admitting different amounts of light, and for the correction
of spherical and chromatic aberration, could have been formed by natural
selection, seems, I freely confess, absurd in the highest possible degree.
Yet reason tells me, that if numerous gradations from a perfect and complex
eye to one very imperfect and simple, each grade being useful to its
possessor, can be shown to exist; if further, the eye does vary ever so
slightly, and the variations be inherited, which is certainly the case; and
if any variation or modification in the organ be ever useful to an animal
under changing conditions of life, then the difficulty of believing that a
perfect and complex eye could be formed by natural selection, though
insuperable by our imagination, can hardly be considered real. How a nerve
comes to be sensitive to light, hardly concerns us more than how life
itself first originated; but I may remark that several facts make me
suspect that any sensitive nerve may be rendered sensitive to light, and
likewise to those coarser vibrations of the air which produce sound.
In looking for the gradations by which an organ in any species has been
perfected, we ought to look exclusively to its lineal ancestors; but this
is scarcely ever possible, and we are forced in each case to look to
species of the same group, that is to the collateral descendants from the
same original parent-form, in order to see what gradations are possible,
and for the chance of some gradations having been transmitted from the
earlier stages of descent, in an unaltered or little altered condition.
Amongst existing Vertebrata, we find but a small amount of gradation in the
structure of the eye, and from fossil species we can learn nothing on this
head. In this great class we should probably have to descend far beneath
the lowest known fossiliferous stratum to discover the earlier stages, by
which the eye has been perfected.
In the Articulata we can commence a series with an optic nerve merely
coated with pigment, and without any other mechanism; and from this low
stage, numerous gradations of structure, branching off in two fundamentally
different lines, can be shown to exist, until we reach a moderately high
stage of perfection. In certain crustaceans, for instance, there is a
double cornea, the inner one divided into facets, within each of which
there is a lens-shaped swelling. In other crustaceans the transparent
cones which are coated by pigment, and which properly act only by excluding
lateral pencils of light, are convex at their upper ends and must act by
convergence; and at their lower ends there seems to be an imperfect
vitreous substance. With these facts, here far too briefly and imperfectly
given, which show that there is much graduated diversity in the eyes of
living crustaceans, and bearing in mind how small the number of living
animals is in proportion to those which have become extinct, I can see no
very great difficulty (not more than in the case of many other structures)
in believing that natural selection has converted the simple apparatus of
an optic nerve merely coated with pigment and invested by transparent
membrane, into an optical instrument as perfect as is possessed by any
member of the great Articulate class.
He who will go thus far, if he find on finishing this treatise that large
bodies of facts, otherwise inexplicable, can be explained by the theory of
descent, ought not to hesitate to go further, and to admit that a structure
even as perfect as the eye of an eagle might be formed by natural
selection, although in this case he does not know any of the transitional
grades. His reason ought to conquer his imagination; though I have felt
the difficulty far too keenly to be surprised at any degree of hesitation
in extending the principle of natural selection to such startling lengths.
It is scarcely possible to avoid comparing the eye to a telescope. We know
that this instrument has been perfected by the long-continued efforts of
the highest human intellects; and we naturally infer that the eye has been
formed by a somewhat analogous process. But may not this inference be
presumptuous? Have we any right to assume that the Creator works by
intellectual powers like those of man? If we must compare the eye to an
optical instrument, we ought in imagination to take a thick layer of
transparent tissue, with a nerve sensitive to light beneath, and then
suppose every part of this layer to be continually changing slowly in
density, so as to separate into layers of different densities and
thicknesses, placed at different distances from each other, and with the
surfaces of each layer slowly changing in form. Further we must suppose
that there is a power always intently watching each slight accidental
alteration in the transparent layers; and carefully selecting each
alteration which, under varied circumstances, may in any way, or in any
degree, tend to produce a distincter image. We must suppose each new state
of the instrument to be multiplied by the million; and each to be preserved
till a better be produced, and then the old ones to be destroyed. In
living bodies, variation will cause the slight alterations, generation will
multiply them almost infinitely, and natural selection will pick out with
unerring skill each improvement. Let this process go on for millions on
millions of years; and during each year on millions of individuals of many
kinds; and may we not believe that a living optical instrument might thus
be formed as superior to one of glass, as the works of the Creator are to
those of man?
If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed, which could not
possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modifications, my
theory would absolutely break down. But I can find out no such case. No
doubt many organs exist of which we do not know the transitional grades,
more especially if we look to much-isolated species, round which, according
to my theory, there has been much extinction. Or again, if we look to an
organ common to all the members of a large class, for in this latter case
the organ must have been first formed at an extremely remote period, since
which all the many members of the class have been developed; and in order
to discover the early transitional grades through which the organ has
passed, we should have to look to very ancient ancestral forms, long since
become extinct.
We should be extremely cautious in concluding that an organ could not have
been formed by transitional gradations of some kind. Numerous cases could
be given amongst the lower animals of the same organ performing at the same
time wholly distinct functions; thus the alimentary canal respires,
digests, and excretes in the larva of the dragon-fly and in the fish
Cobites. In the Hydra, the animal may be turned inside out, and the
exterior surface will then digest and the stomach respire. In such cases
natural selection might easily specialise, if any advantage were thus
gained, a part or organ, which had performed two functions, for one
function alone, and thus wholly change its nature by insensible steps. Two
distinct organs sometimes perform simultaneously the same function in the
same individual; to give one instance, there are fish with gills or
branchiae that breathe the air dissolved in the water, at the same time
that they breathe free air in their swimbladders, this latter organ having
a ductus pneumaticus for its supply, and being divided by highly vascular
partitions. In these cases, one of the two organs might with ease be
modified and perfected so as to perform all the work by itself, being aided
during the process of modification by the other organ; and then this other
organ might be modified for some other and quite distinct purpose, or be
quite obliterated.
The illustration of the swimbladder in fishes is a good one, because it
shows us clearly the highly important fact that an organ originally
constructed for one purpose, namely flotation, may be converted into one
for a wholly different purpose, namely respiration. The swimbladder has,
also, been worked in as an accessory to the auditory organs of certain
fish, or, for I do not know which view is now generally held, a part of the
auditory apparatus has been worked in as a complement to the swimbladder.
All physiologists admit that the swimbladder is homologous, or 'ideally
similar,' in position and structure with the lungs of the higher vertebrate
animals: hence there seems to me to be no great difficulty in believing
that natural selection has actually converted a swimbladder into a lung, or
organ used exclusively for respiration.
I can, indeed, hardly doubt that all vertebrate animals having true lungs
have descended by ordinary generation from an ancient prototype, of which
we know nothing, furnished with a floating apparatus or swimbladder. We
can thus, as I infer from Professor Owen's interesting description of these
parts, understand the strange fact that every particle of food and drink
which we swallow has to pass over the orifice of the trachea, with some
risk of falling into the lungs, notwithstanding the beautiful contrivance
by which the glottis is closed. In the higher Vertebrata the branchiae
have wholly disappeared--the slits on the sides of the neck and the
loop-like course of the arteries still marking in the embryo their former
position. But it is conceivable that the now utterly lost branchiae might
have been gradually worked in by natural selection for some quite distinct
purpose: in the same manner as, on the view entertained by some
naturalists that the branchiae and dorsal scales of Annelids are homologous
with the wings and wing-covers of insects, it is probable that organs which
at a very ancient period served for respiration have been actually
converted into organs of flight.
In considering transitions of organs, it is so important to bear in mind
the probability of conversion from one function to another, that I will
give one more instance. Pedunculated cirripedes have two minute folds of
skin, called by me the ovigerous frena, which serve, through the means of a
sticky secretion, to retain the eggs until they are hatched within the
sack. These cirripedes have no branchiae, the whole surface of the body
and sack, including the small frena, serving for respiration. The
Balanidae or sessile cirripedes, on the other hand, have no ovigerous
frena, the eggs lying loose at the bottom of the sack, in the well-enclosed
shell; but they have large folded branchiae. Now I think no one will
dispute that the ovigerous frena in the one family are strictly homologous
with the branchiae of the other family; indeed, they graduate into each
other. Therefore I do not doubt that little folds of skin, which
originally served as ovigerous frena, but which, likewise, very slightly
aided the act of respiration, have been gradually converted by natural
selection into branchiae, simply through an increase in their size and the
obliteration of their adhesive glands. If all pedunculated cirripedes had
become extinct, and they have already suffered far more extinction than
have sessile cirripedes, who would ever have imagined that the branchiae in
this latter family had originally existed as organs for preventing the ova
from being washed out of the sack?
Although we must be extremely cautious in concluding that any organ could
not possibly have been produced by successive transitional gradations, yet,
undoubtedly, grave cases of difficulty occur, some of which will be
discussed in my future work.
One of the gravest is that of neuter insects, which are often very
differently constructed from either the males or fertile females; but this
case will be treated of in the next chapter. The electric organs of fishes
offer another case of special difficulty; it is impossible to conceive by
what steps these wondrous organs have been produced; but, as Owen and
others have remarked, their intimate structure closely resembles that of
common muscle; and as it has lately been shown that Rays have an organ
closely analogous to the electric apparatus, and yet do not, as Matteuchi
asserts, discharge any electricity, we must own that we are far too
ignorant to argue that no transition of any kind is possible.
The electric organs offer another and even more serious difficulty; for
they occur in only about a dozen fishes, of which several are widely remote
in their affinities. Generally when the same organ appears in several
members of the same class, especially if in members having very different
habits of life, we may attribute its presence to inheritance from a common
ancestor; and its absence in some of the members to its loss through disuse
or natural selection. But if the electric organs had been inherited from
one ancient progenitor thus provided, we might have expected that all
electric fishes would have been specially related to each other. Nor does
geology at all lead to the belief that formerly most fishes had electric
organs, which most of their modified descendants have lost. The presence
of luminous organs in a few insects, belonging to different families and
orders, offers a parallel case of difficulty. Other cases could be given;
for instance in plants, the very curious contrivance of a mass of
pollen-grains, borne on a foot-stalk with a sticky gland at the end, is the
same in Orchis and Asclepias,--genera almost as remote as possible amongst
flowering plants. In all these cases of two very distinct species
furnished with apparently the same anomalous organ, it should be observed
that, although the general appearance and function of the organ may be the
same, yet some fundamental difference can generally be detected. I am
inclined to believe that in nearly the same way as two men have sometimes
independently hit on the very same invention, so natural selection, working
for the good of each being and taking advantage of analogous variations,
has sometimes modified in very nearly the same manner two parts in two
organic beings, which owe but little of their structure in common to
inheritance from the same ancestor.
Although in many cases it is most difficult to conjecture by what
transitions an organ could have arrived at its present state; yet,
considering that the proportion of living and known forms to the extinct
and unknown is very small, I have been astonished how rarely an organ can
be named, towards which no transitional grade is known to lead. The truth
of this remark is indeed shown by that old canon in natural history of
'Natura non facit saltum.' We meet with this admission in the writings of
almost every experienced naturalist; or, as Milne Edwards has well
expressed it, nature is prodigal in variety, but niggard in innovation.
Why, on the theory of Creation, should this be so? Why should all the
parts and organs of many independent beings, each supposed to have been
separately created for its proper place in nature, be so invariably linked
together by graduated steps? Why should not Nature have taken a leap from
structure to structure? On the theory of natural selection, we can clearly
understand why she should not; for natural selection can act only by taking
advantage of slight successive variations; she can never take a leap, but
must advance by the shortest and slowest steps.
Organs of little apparent importance. -- As natural selection acts by life
and death,--by the preservation of individuals with any favourable
variation, and by the destruction of those with any unfavourable deviation
of structure,--I have sometimes felt much difficulty in understanding the
origin of simple parts, of which the importance does not seem sufficient to
cause the preservation of successively varying individuals. I have
sometimes felt as much difficulty, though of a very different kind, on this
head, as in the case of an organ as perfect and complex as the eye.
In the first place, we are much too ignorant in regard to the whole economy
of any one organic being, to say what slight modifications would be of
importance or not. In a former chapter I have given instances of most
trifling characters, such as the down on fruit and the colour of the flesh,
which, from determining the attacks of insects or from being correlated
with constitutional differences, might assuredly be acted on by natural
selection. The tail of the giraffe looks like an artificially constructed
fly-flapper; and it seems at first incredible that this could have been
adapted for its present purpose by successive slight modifications, each
better and better, for so trifling an object as driving away flies; yet we
should pause before being too positive even in this case, for we know that
the distribution and existence of cattle and other animals in South America
absolutely depends on their power of resisting the attacks of insects: so
that individuals which could by any means defend themselves from these
small enemies, would be able to range into new pastures and thus gain a
great advantage. It is not that the larger quadrupeds are actually
destroyed (except in some rare cases) by the flies, but they are
incessantly harassed and their strength reduced, so that they are more
subject to disease, or not so well enabled in a coming dearth to search for
food, or to escape from beasts of prey.
Organs now of trifling importance have probably in some cases been of high
importance to an early progenitor, and, after having been slowly perfected
at a former period, have been transmitted in nearly the same state,
although now become of very slight use; and any actually injurious
deviations in their structure will always have been checked by natural
selection. Seeing how important an organ of locomotion the tail is in most
aquatic animals, its general presence and use for many purposes in so many
land animals, which in their lungs or modified swim-bladders betray their
aquatic origin, may perhaps be thus accounted for. A well-developed tail
having been formed in an aquatic animal, it might subsequently come to be
worked in for all sorts of purposes, as a fly-flapper, an organ of
prehension, or as an aid in turning, as with the dog, though the aid must
be slight, for the hare, with hardly any tail, can double quickly enough.
In the second place, we may sometimes attribute importance to characters
which are really of very little importance, and which have originated from
quite secondary causes, independently of natural selection. We should
remember that climate, food, &c., probably have some little direct
influence on the organisation; that characters reappear from the law of
reversion; that correlation of growth will have had a most important
influence in modifying various structures; and finally, that sexual
selection will often have largely modified the external characters of
animals having a will, to give one male an advantage in fighting with
another or in charming the females. Moreover when a modification of
structure has primarily arisen from the above or other unknown causes, it
may at first have been of no advantage to the species, but may subsequently
have been taken advantage of by the descendants of the species under new
conditions of life and with newly acquired habits.
To give a few instances to illustrate these latter remarks. If green
woodpeckers alone had existed, and we did not know that there were many
black and pied kinds, I dare say that we should have thought that the green
colour was a beautiful adaptation to hide this tree-frequenting bird from
its enemies; and consequently that it was a character of importance and
might have been acquired through natural selection; as it is, I have no
doubt that the colour is due to some quite distinct cause, probably to
sexual selection. A trailing bamboo in the Malay Archipelago climbs the
loftiest trees by the aid of exquisitely constructed hooks clustered around
the ends of the branches, and this contrivance, no doubt, is of the highest
service to the plant; but as we see nearly similar hooks on many trees
which are not climbers, the hooks on the bamboo may have arisen from
unknown laws of growth, and have been subsequently taken advantage of by
the plant undergoing further modification and becoming a climber. The
naked skin on the head of a vulture is generally looked at as a direct
adaptation for wallowing in putridity; and so it may be, or it may possibly
be due to the direct action of putrid matter; but we should be very
cautious in drawing any such inference, when we see that the skin on the
head of the clean-feeding male turkey is likewise naked. The sutures in
the skulls of young mammals have been advanced as a beautiful adaptation
for aiding parturition, and no doubt they facilitate, or may be
indispensable for this act; but as sutures occur in the skulls of young
birds and reptiles, which have only to escape from a broken egg, we may
infer that this structure has arisen from the laws of growth, and has been
taken advantage of in the parturition of the higher animals.
We are profoundly ignorant of the causes producing slight and unimportant
variations; and we are immediately made conscious of this by reflecting on
the differences in the breeds of our domesticated animals in different
countries,--more especially in the less civilized countries where there has
been but little artificial selection. Careful observers are convinced that
a damp climate affects the growth of the hair, and that with the hair the
horns are correlated. Mountain breeds always differ from lowland breeds;
and a mountainous country would probably affect the hind limbs from
exercising them more, and possibly even the form of the pelvis; and then by
the law of homologous variation, the front limbs and even the head would
probably be affected. The shape, also, of the pelvis might affect by
pressure the shape of the head of the young in the womb. The laborious
breathing necessary in high regions would, we have some reason to believe,
increase the size of the chest; and again correlation would come into play.
Animals kept by savages in different countries often have to struggle for
their own subsistence, and would be exposed to a certain extent to natural
selection, and individuals with slightly different constitutions would
succeed best under different climates; and there is reason to believe that
constitution and colour are correlated. A good observer, also, states that
in cattle susceptibility to the attacks of flies is correlated with colour,
as is the liability to be poisoned by certain plants; so that colour would
be thus subjected to the action of natural selection. But we are far too
ignorant to speculate on the relative importance of the several known and
unknown laws of variation; and I have here alluded to them only to show
that, if we are unable to account for the characteristic differences of our
domestic breeds, which nevertheless we generally admit to have arisen
through ordinary generation, we ought not to lay too much stress on our
ignorance of the precise cause of the slight analogous differences between
species. I might have adduced for this same purpose the differences
between the races of man, which are so strongly marked; I may add that some
little light can apparently be thrown on the origin of these differences,
chiefly through sexual selection of a particular kind, but without here
entering on copious details my reasoning would appear frivolous.
The foregoing remarks lead me to say a few words on the protest lately made
by some naturalists, against the utilitarian doctrine that every detail of
structure has been produced for the good of its possessor. They believe
that very many structures have been created for beauty in the eyes of man,
or for mere variety. This doctrine, if true, would be absolutely fatal to
my theory. Yet I fully admit that many structures are of no direct use to
their possessors. Physical conditions probably have had some little effect
on structure, quite independently of any good thus gained. Correlation of
growth has no doubt played a most important part, and a useful modification
of one part will often have entailed on other parts diversified changes of
no direct use. So again characters which formerly were useful, or which
formerly had arisen from correlation of growth, or from other unknown
cause, may reappear from the law of reversion, though now of no direct use.
The effects of sexual selection, when displayed in beauty to charm the
females, can be called useful only in rather a forced sense. But by far
the most important consideration is that the chief part of the organisation
of every being is simply due to inheritance; and consequently, though each
being assuredly is well fitted for its place in nature, many structures now
have no direct relation to the habits of life of each species. Thus, we
can hardly believe that the webbed feet of the upland goose or of the
frigate-bird are of special use to these birds; we cannot believe that the
same bones in the arm of the monkey, in the fore leg of the horse, in the
wing of the bat, and in the flipper of the seal, are of special use to
these animals. We may safely attribute these structures to inheritance.
But to the progenitor of the upland goose and of the frigate-bird, webbed
feet no doubt were as useful as they now are to the most aquatic of
existing birds. So we may believe that the progenitor of the seal had not
a flipper, but a foot with five toes fitted for walking or grasping; and we
may further venture to believe that the several bones in the limbs of the
monkey, horse, and bat, which have been inherited from a common progenitor,
were formerly of more special use to that progenitor, or its progenitors,
than they now are to these animals having such widely diversified habits.
Therefore we may infer that these several bones might have been acquired
through natural selection, subjected formerly, as now, to the several laws
of inheritance, reversion, correlation of growth, &c. Hence every detail
of structure in every living creature (making some little allowance for the
direct action of physical conditions) may be viewed, either as having been
of special use to some ancestral form, or as being now of special use to
the descendants of this form--either directly, or indirectly through the
complex laws of growth.
Natural selection cannot possibly produce any modification in any one
species exclusively for the good of another species; though throughout
nature one species incessantly takes advantage of, and profits by, the
structure of another. But natural selection can and does often produce
structures for the direct injury of other species, as we see in the fang of
the adder, and in the ovipositor of the ichneumon, by which its eggs are
deposited in the living bodies of other insects. If it could be proved
that any part of the structure of any one species had been formed for the
exclusive good of another species, it would annihilate my theory, for such
could not have been produced through natural selection. Although many
statements may be found in works on natural history to this effect, I
cannot find even one which seems to me of any weight. It is admitted that
the rattlesnake has a poison-fang for its own defence and for the
destruction of its prey; but some authors suppose that at the same time
this snake is furnished with a rattle for its own injury, namely, to warn
its prey to escape. I would almost as soon believe that the cat curls the
end of its tail when preparing to spring, in order to warn the doomed
mouse. But I have not space here to enter on this and other such cases.
Natural selection will never produce in a being anything injurious to
itself, for natural selection acts solely by and for the good of each. No
organ will be formed, as Paley has remarked, for the purpose of causing
pain or for doing an injury to its possessor. If a fair balance be struck
between the good and evil caused by each part, each will be found on the
whole advantageous. After the lapse of time, under changing conditions of
life, if any part comes to be injurious, it will be modified; or if it be
not so, the being will become extinct, as myriads have become extinct.
Natural selection tends only to make each organic being as perfect as, or
slightly more perfect than, the other inhabitants of the same country with
which it has to struggle for existence. And we see that this is the degree
of perfection attained under nature. The endemic productions of New
Zealand, for instance, are perfect one compared with another; but they are
now rapidly yielding before the advancing legions of plants and animals
introduced from Europe. Natural selection will not produce absolute
perfection, nor do we always meet, as far as we can judge, with this high
standard under nature. The correction for the aberration of light is said,
on high authority, not to be perfect even in that most perfect organ, the
eye. If our reason leads us to admire with enthusiasm a multitude of
inimitable contrivances in nature, this same reason tells us, though we may
easily err on both sides, that some other contrivances are less perfect.
Can we consider the sting of the wasp or of the bee as perfect, which, when
used against many attacking animals, cannot be withdrawn, owing to the
backward serratures, and so inevitably causes the death of the insect by
tearing out its viscera?
If we look at the sting of the bee, as having originally existed in a
remote progenitor as a boring and serrated instrument, like that in so many
members of the same great order, and which has been modified but not
perfected for its present purpose, with the poison originally adapted to
cause galls subsequently intensified, we can perhaps understand how it is
that the use of the sting should so often cause the insect's own death:
for if on the whole the power of stinging be useful to the community, it
will fulfil all the requirements of natural selection, though it may cause
the death of some few members. If we admire the truly wonderful power of
scent by which the males of many insects find their females, can we admire
the production for this single purpose of thousands of drones, which are
utterly useless to the community for any other end, and which are
ultimately slaughtered by their industrious and sterile sisters? It may be
difficult, but we ought to admire the savage instinctive hatred of the
queen-bee, which urges her instantly to destroy the young queens her
daughters as soon as born, or to perish herself in the combat; for
undoubtedly this is for the good of the community; and maternal love or
maternal hatred, though the latter fortunately is most rare, is all the
same to the inexorable principle of natural selection. If we admire the
several ingenious contrivances, by which the flowers of the orchis and of
many other plants are fertilised through insect agency, can we consider as
equally perfect the elaboration by our fir-trees of dense clouds of pollen,
in order that a few granules may be wafted by a chance breeze on to the
ovules?
Summary of Chapter -- We have in this chapter discussed some of the
difficulties and objections which may be urged against my theory. Many of
them are very grave; but I think that in the discussion light has been
thrown on several facts, which on the theory of independent acts of
creation are utterly obscure. We have seen that species at any one period
are not indefinitely variable, and are not linked together by a multitude
of intermediate gradations, partly because the process of natural selection
will always be very slow, and will act, at any one time, only on a very few
forms; and partly because the very process of natural selection almost
implies the continual supplanting and extinction of preceding and
intermediate gradations. Closely allied species, now living on a
continuous area, must often have been formed when the area was not
continuous, and when the conditions of life did not insensibly graduate
away from one part to another. When two varieties are formed in two
districts of a continuous area, an intermediate variety will often be
formed, fitted for an intermediate zone; but from reasons assigned, the
intermediate variety will usually exist in lesser numbers than the two
forms which it connects; consequently the two latter, during the course of
further modification, from existing in greater numbers, will have a great
advantage over the less numerous intermediate variety, and will thus
generally succeed in supplanting and exterminating it.
We have seen in this chapter how cautious we should be in concluding that
the most different habits of life could not graduate into each other; that
a bat, for instance, could not have been formed by natural selection from
an animal which at first could only glide through the air.
We have seen that a species may under new conditions of life change its
habits, or have diversified habits, with some habits very unlike those of
its nearest congeners. Hence we can understand, bearing in mind that each
organic being is trying to live wherever it can live, how it has arisen
that there are upland geese with webbed feet, ground woodpeckers, diving
thrushes, and petrels with the habits of auks.
Although the belief that an organ so perfect as the eye could have been
formed by natural selection, is more than enough to stagger any one; yet in
the case of any organ, if we know of a long series of gradations in
complexity, each good for its possessor, then, under changing conditions of
life, there is no logical impossibility in the acquirement of any
conceivable degree of perfection through natural selection. In the cases
in which we know of no intermediate or transitional states, we should be
very cautious in concluding that none could have existed, for the
homologies of many organs and their intermediate states show that wonderful
metamorphoses in function are at least possible. For instance, a
swim-bladder has apparently been converted into an air-breathing lung. The
same organ having performed simultaneously very different functions, and
then having been specialised for one function; and two very distinct organs
having performed at the same time the same function, the one having been
perfected whilst aided by the other, must often have largely facilitated
transitions.
We are far too ignorant, in almost every case, to be enabled to assert that
any part or organ is so unimportant for the welfare of a species, that
modifications in its structure could not have been slowly accumulated by
means of natural selection. But we may confidently believe that many
modifications, wholly due to the laws of growth, and at first in no way
advantageous to a species, have been subsequently taken advantage of by the
still further modified descendants of this species. We may, also, believe
that a part formerly of high importance has often been retained (as the
tail of an aquatic animal by its terrestrial descendants), though it has
become of such small importance that it could not, in its present state,
have been acquired by natural selection,--a power which acts solely by the
preservation of profitable variations in the struggle for life.
Natural selection will produce nothing in one species for the exclusive
good or injury of another; though it may well produce parts, organs, and
excretions highly useful or even indispensable, or highly injurious to
another species, but in all cases at the same time useful to the owner.
Natural selection in each well-stocked country, must act chiefly through
the competition of the inhabitants one with another, and consequently will
produce perfection, or strength in the battle for life, only according to
the standard of that country. Hence the inhabitants of one country,
generally the smaller one, will often yield, as we see they do yield, to
the inhabitants of another and generally larger country. For in the larger
country there will have existed more individuals, and more diversified
forms, and the competition will have been severer, and thus the standard of
perfection will have been rendered higher. Natural selection will not
necessarily produce absolute perfection; nor, as far as we can judge by our
limited faculties, can absolute perfection be everywhere found.
On the theory of natural selection we can clearly understand the full
meaning of that old canon in natural history, 'Natura non facit saltum.'
This canon, if we look only to the present inhabitants of the world, is not
strictly correct, but if we include all those of past times, it must by my
theory be strictly true.
It is generally acknowledged that all organic beings have been formed on
two great laws--Unity of Type, and the Conditions of Existence. By unity
of type is meant that fundamental agreement in structure, which we see in
organic beings of the same class, and which is quite independent of their
habits of life. On my theory, unity of type is explained by unity of
descent. The expression of conditions of existence, so often insisted on
by the illustrious Cuvier, is fully embraced by the principle of natural
selection. For natural selection acts by either now adapting the varying
parts of each being to its organic and inorganic conditions of life; or by
having adapted them during long-past periods of time: the adaptations
being aided in some cases by use and disuse, being slightly affected by the
direct action of the external conditions of life, and being in all cases
subjected to the several laws of growth. Hence, in fact, the law of the
Conditions of Existence is the higher law; as it includes, through the
inheritance of former adaptations, that of Unity of Type.