Chapter XIII
Mutual Affinities of Organic Beings:
Morphology: Embryology: Rudimentary Organs
Classification, groups subordinate to groups -- Natural system -- Rules and
difficulties in classification, explained on the theory of descent with
modification -- Classification of varieties -- Descent always used in
classification -- Analogical or adaptive characters -- Affinities, general,
complex and radiating -- Extinction separates and defines groups --
Morphology, between members of the same class, between parts of the same
individual -- Embryology, laws of, explained by variations not supervening
at an early age, and being inherited at a corresponding age -- Rudimentary
Organs; their origin explained -- Summary.
From the first dawn of life, all organic beings are found to resemble each
other in descending degrees, so that they can be classed in groups under
groups. This classification is evidently not arbitrary like the grouping
of the stars in constellations. The existence of groups would have been of
simple signification, if one group had been exclusively fitted to inhabit
the land, and another the water; one to feed on flesh, another on vegetable
matter, and so on; but the case is widely different in nature; for it is
notorious how commonly members of even the same subgroup have different
habits. In our second and fourth chapters, on Variation and on Natural
Selection, I have attempted to show that it is the widely ranging, the much
diffused and common, that is the dominant species belonging to the larger
genera, which vary most. The varieties, or incipient species, thus
produced ultimately become converted, as I believe, into new and distinct
species; and these, on the principle of inheritance, tend to produce other
new and dominant species. Consequently the groups which are now large, and
which generally include many dominant species, tend to go on increasing
indefinitely in size. I further attempted to show that from the varying
descendants of each species trying to occupy as many and as different
places as possible in the economy of nature, there is a constant tendency
in their characters to diverge. This conclusion was supported by looking
at the great diversity of the forms of life which, in any small area, come
into the closest competition, and by looking to certain facts in
naturalisation.
I attempted also to show that there is a constant tendency in the forms
which are increasing in number and diverging in character, to supplant and
exterminate the less divergent, the less improved, and preceding forms. I
request the reader to turn to the diagram illustrating the action, as
formerly explained, of these several principles; and he will see that the
inevitable result is that the modified descendants proceeding from one
progenitor become broken up into groups subordinate to groups. In the
diagram each letter on the uppermost line may represent a genus including
several species; and all the genera on this line form together one class,
for all have descended from one ancient but unseen parent, and,
consequently, have inherited something in common. But the three genera on
the left hand have, on this same principle, much in common, and form a
sub-family, distinct from that including the next two genera on the right
hand, which diverged from a common parent at the fifth stage of descent.
These five genera have also much, though less, in common; and they form a
family distinct from that including the three genera still further to the
right hand, which diverged at a still earlier period. And all these
genera, descended from (A), form an order distinct from the genera
descended from (I). So that we here have many species descended from a
single progenitor grouped into genera; and the genera are included in, or
subordinate to, sub-families, families, and orders, all united into one
class. Thus, the grand fact in natural history of the subordination of
group under group, which, from its familiarity, does not always
sufficiently strike us, is in my judgment fully explained.
Naturalists try to arrange the species, genera, and families in each class,
on what is called the Natural System. But what is meant by this system?
Some authors look at it merely as a scheme for arranging together those
living objects which are most alike, and for separating those which are
most unlike; or as an artificial means for enunciating, as briefly as
possible, general propositions,--that is, by one sentence to give the
characters common, for instance, to all mammals, by another those common to
all carnivora, by another those common to the dog-genus, and then by adding
a single sentence, a full description is given of each kind of dog. The
ingenuity and utility of this system are indisputable. But many
naturalists think that something more is meant by the Natural System; they
believe that it reveals the plan of the Creator; but unless it be specified
whether order in time or space, or what else is meant by the plan of the
Creator, it seems to me that nothing is thus added to our knowledge. Such
expressions as that famous one of Linnaeus, and which we often meet with in
a more or less concealed form, that the characters do not make the genus,
but that the genus gives the characters, seem to imply that something more
is included in our classification, than mere resemblance. I believe that
something more is included; and that propinquity of descent,--the only
known cause of the similarity of organic beings,--is the bond, hidden as it
is by various degrees of modification, which is partially revealed to us by
our classifications.
Let us now consider the rules followed in classification, and the
difficulties which are encountered on the view that classification either
gives some unknown plan of creation, or is simply a scheme for enunciating
general propositions and of placing together the forms most like each
other. It might have been thought (and was in ancient times thought) that
those parts of the structure which determined the habits of life, and the
general place of each being in the economy of nature, would be of very high
importance in classification. Nothing can be more false. No one regards
the external similarity of a mouse to a shrew, of a dugong to a whale, of a
whale to a fish, as of any importance. These resemblances, though so
intimately connected with the whole life of the being, are ranked as merely
'adaptive or analogical characters;' but to the consideration of these
resemblances we shall have to recur. It may even be given as a general
rule, that the less any part of the organisation is concerned with special
habits, the more important it becomes for classification. As an instance:
Owen, in speaking of the dugong, says, 'The generative organs being those
which are most remotely related to the habits and food of an animal, I have
always regarded as affording very clear indications of its true affinities.
We are least likely in the modifications of these organs to mistake a
merely adaptive for an essential character.' So with plants, how
remarkable it is that the organs of vegetation, on which their whole life
depends, are of little signification, excepting in the first main
divisions; whereas the organs of reproduction, with their product the seed,
are of paramount importance!
We must not, therefore, in classifying, trust to resemblances in parts of
the organisation, however important they may be for the welfare of the
being in relation to the outer world. Perhaps from this cause it has
partly arisen, that almost all naturalists lay the greatest stress on
resemblances in organs of high vital or physiological importance. No doubt
this view of the classificatory importance of organs which are important is
generally, but by no means always, true. But their importance for
classification, I believe, depends on their greater constancy throughout
large groups of species; and this constancy depends on such organs having
generally been subjected to less change in the adaptation of the species to
their conditions of life. That the mere physiological importance of an
organ does not determine its classificatory value, is almost shown by the
one fact, that in allied groups, in which the same organ, as we have every
reason to suppose, has nearly the same physiological value, its
classificatory value is widely different. No naturalist can have worked at
any group without being struck with this fact; and it has been most fully
acknowledged in the writings of almost every author. It will suffice to
quote the highest authority, Robert Brown, who in speaking of certain
organs in the Proteaceae, says their generic importance, 'like that of all
their parts, not only in this but, as I apprehend, in every natural family,
is very unequal, and in some cases seems to be entirely lost.' Again in
another work he says, the genera of the Connaraceae 'differ in having one
or more ovaria, in the existence or absence of albumen, in the imbricate or
valvular aestivation. Any one of these characters singly is frequently of
more than generic importance, though here even when all taken together they
appear insufficient to separate Cnestis from Connarus.' To give an example
amongst insects, in one great division of the Hymenoptera, the antennae, as
Westwood has remarked, are most constant in structure; in another division
they differ much, and the differences are of quite subordinate value in
classification; yet no one probably will say that the antennae in these two
divisions of the same order are of unequal physiological importance. Any
number of instances could be given of the varying importance for
classification of the same important organ within the same group of beings.
Again, no one will say that rudimentary or atrophied organs are of high
physiological or vital importance; yet, undoubtedly, organs in this
condition are often of high value in classification. No one will dispute
that the rudimentary teeth in the upper jaws of young ruminants, and
certain rudimentary bones of the leg, are highly serviceable in exhibiting
the close affinity between Ruminants and Pachyderms. Robert Brown has
strongly insisted on the fact that the rudimentary florets are of the
highest importance in the classification of the Grasses.
Numerous instances could be given of characters derived from parts which
must be considered of very trifling physiological importance, but which are
universally admitted as highly serviceable in the definition of whole
groups. For instance, whether or not there is an open passage from the
nostrils to the mouth, the only character, according to Owen, which
absolutely distinguishes fishes and reptiles--the inflection of the angle
of the jaws in Marsupials--the manner in which the wings of insects are
folded--mere colour in certain Algae--mere pubescence on parts of the
flower in grasses--the nature of the dermal covering, as hair or feathers,
in the Vertebrata. If the Ornithorhynchus had been covered with feathers
instead of hair, this external and trifling character would, I think, have
been considered by naturalists as important an aid in determining the
degree of affinity of this strange creature to birds and reptiles, as an
approach in structure in any one internal and important organ.
The importance, for classification, of trifling characters, mainly depends
on their being correlated with several other characters of more or less
importance. The value indeed of an aggregate of characters is very evident
in natural history. Hence, as has often been remarked, a species may
depart from its allies in several characters, both of high physiological
importance and of almost universal prevalence, and yet leave us in no doubt
where it should be ranked. Hence, also, it has been found, that a
classification founded on any single character, however important that may
be, has always failed; for no part of the organisation is universally
constant. The importance of an aggregate of characters, even when none are
important, alone explains, I think, that saying of Linnaeus, that the
characters do not give the genus, but the genus gives the characters; for
this saying seems founded on an appreciation of many trifling points of
resemblance, too slight to be defined. Certain plants, belonging to the
Malpighiaceae, bear perfect and degraded flowers; in the latter, as A. de
Jussieu has remarked, 'the greater number of the characters proper to the
species, to the genus, to the family, to the class, disappear, and thus
laugh at our classification.' But when Aspicarpa produced in France,
during several years, only degraded flowers, departing so wonderfully in a
number of the most important points of structure from the proper type of
the order, yet M. Richard sagaciously saw, as Jussieu observes, that this
genus should still be retained amongst the Malpighiaceae. This case seems
to me well to illustrate the spirit with which our classifications are
sometimes necessarily founded.
Practically when naturalists are at work, they do not trouble themselves
about the physiological value of the characters which they use in defining
a group, or in allocating any particular species. If they find a character
nearly uniform, and common to a great number of forms, and not common to
others, they use it as one of high value; if common to some lesser number,
they use it as of subordinate value. This principle has been broadly
confessed by some naturalists to be the true one; and by none more clearly
than by that excellent botanist, Aug. St. Hilaire. If certain characters
are always found correlated with others, though no apparent bond of
connexion can be discovered between them, especial value is set on them.
As in most groups of animals, important organs, such as those for
propelling the blood, or for aerating it, or those for propagating the
race, are found nearly uniform, they are considered as highly serviceable
in classification; but in some groups of animals all these, the most
important vital organs, are found to offer characters of quite subordinate
value.
We can see why characters derived from the embryo should be of equal
importance with those derived from the adult, for our classifications of
course include all ages of each species. But it is by no means obvious, on
the ordinary view, why the structure of the embryo should be more important
for this purpose than that of the adult, which alone plays its full part in
the economy of nature. Yet it has been strongly urged by those great
naturalists, Milne Edwards and Agassiz, that embryonic characters are the
most important of any in the classification of animals; and this doctrine
has very generally been admitted as true. The same fact holds good with
flowering plants, of which the two main divisions have been founded on
characters derived from the embryo,--on the number and position of the
embryonic leaves or cotyledons, and on the mode of development of the
plumule and radicle. In our discussion on embryology, we shall see why
such characters are so valuable, on the view of classification tacitly
including the idea of descent.
Our classifications are often plainly influenced by chains of affinities.
Nothing can be easier than to define a number of characters common to all
birds; but in the case of crustaceans, such definition has hitherto been
found impossible. There are crustaceans at the opposite ends of the
series, which have hardly a character in common; yet the species at both
ends, from being plainly allied to others, and these to others, and so
onwards, can be recognised as unequivocally belonging to this, and to no
other class of the Articulata.
Geographical distribution has often been used, though perhaps not quite
logically, in classification, more especially in very large groups of
closely allied forms. Temminck insists on the utility or even necessity of
this practice in certain groups of birds; and it has been followed by
several entomologists and botanists.
Finally, with respect to the comparative value of the various groups of
species, such as orders, sub-orders, families, sub-families, and genera,
they seem to be, at least at present, almost arbitrary. Several of the
best botanists, such as Mr. Bentham and others, have strongly insisted on
their arbitrary value. Instances could be given amongst plants and
insects, of a group of forms, first ranked by practised naturalists as only
a genus, and then raised to the rank of a sub-family or family; and this
has been done, not because further research has detected important
structural differences, at first overlooked, but because numerous allied
species, with slightly different grades of difference, have been
subsequently discovered.
All the foregoing rules and aids and difficulties in classification are
explained, if I do not greatly deceive myself, on the view that the natural
system is founded on descent with modification; that the characters which
naturalists consider as showing true affinity between any two or more
species, are those which have been inherited from a common parent, and, in
so far, all true classification is genealogical; that community of descent
is the hidden bond which naturalists have been unconsciously seeking, and
not some unknown plan of creation, or the enunciation of general
propositions, and the mere putting together and separating objects more or
less alike.
But I must explain my meaning more fully. I believe that the arrangement
of the groups within each class, in due subordination and relation to the
other groups, must be strictly genealogical in order to be natural; but
that the amount of difference in the several branches or groups, though
allied in the same degree in blood to their common progenitor, may differ
greatly, being due to the different degrees of modification which they have
undergone; and this is expressed by the forms being ranked under different
genera, families, sections, or orders. The reader will best understand
what is meant, if he will take the trouble of referring to the diagram in
the fourth chapter. We will suppose the letters A to L to represent allied
genera, which lived during the Silurian epoch, and these have descended
from a species which existed at an unknown anterior period. Species of
three of these genera (A, F, and I) have transmitted modified descendants
to the present day, represented by the fifteen genera (a14 to z14) on the
uppermost horizontal line. Now all these modified descendants from a
single species, are represented as related in blood or descent to the same
degree; they may metaphorically be called cousins to the same millionth
degree; yet they differ widely and in different degrees from each other.
The forms descended from A, now broken up into two or three families,
constitute a distinct order from those descended from I, also broken up
into two families. Nor can the existing species, descended from A, be
ranked in the same genus with the parent A; or those from I, with the
parent I. But the existing genus F14 may be supposed to have been but
slightly modified; and it will then rank with the parent-genus F; just as
some few still living organic beings belong to Silurian genera. So that
the amount or value of the differences between organic beings all related
to each other in the same degree in blood, has come to be widely different.
Nevertheless their genealogical arrangement remains strictly true, not only
at the present time, but at each successive period of descent. All the
modified descendants from A will have inherited something in common from
their common parent, as will all the descendants from I; so will it be with
each subordinate branch of descendants, at each successive period. If,
however, we choose to suppose that any of the descendants of A or of I have
been so much modified as to have more or less completely lost traces of
their parentage, in this case, their places in a natural classification
will have been more or less completely lost,--as sometimes seems to have
occurred with existing organisms. All the descendants of the genus F,
along its whole line of descent, are supposed to have been but little
modified, and they yet form a single genus. But this genus, though much
isolated, will still occupy its proper intermediate position; for F
originally was intermediate in character between A and I, and the several
genera descended from these two genera will have inherited to a certain
extent their characters. This natural arrangement is shown, as far as is
possible on paper, in the diagram, but in much too simple a manner. If a
branching diagram had not been used, and only the names of the groups had
been written in a linear series, it would have been still less possible to
have given a natural arrangement; and it is notoriously not possible to
represent in a series, on a flat surface, the affinities which we discover
in nature amongst the beings of the same group. Thus, on the view which I
hold, the natural system is genealogical in its arrangement, like a
pedigree; but the degrees of modification which the different groups have
undergone, have to be expressed by ranking them under different so-called
genera, sub-families, families, sections, orders, and classes.
It may be worth while to illustrate this view of classification, by taking
the case of languages. If we possessed a perfect pedigree of mankind, a
genealogical arrangement of the races of man would afford the best
classification of the various languages now spoken throughout the world;
and if all extinct languages, and all intermediate and slowly changing
dialects, had to be included, such an arrangement would, I think, be the
only possible one. Yet it might be that some very ancient language had
altered little, and had given rise to few new languages, whilst others
(owing to the spreading and subsequent isolation and states of civilisation
of the several races, descended from a common race) had altered much, and
had given rise to many new languages and dialects. The various degrees of
difference in the languages from the same stock, would have to be expressed
by groups subordinate to groups; but the proper or even only possible
arrangement would still be genealogical; and this would be strictly
natural, as it would connect together all languages, extinct and modern, by
the closest affinities, and would give the filiation and origin of each
tongue.
In confirmation of this view, let us glance at the classification of
varieties, which are believed or known to have descended from one species.
These are grouped under species, with sub-varieties under varieties; and
with our domestic productions, several other grades of difference are
requisite, as we have seen with pigeons. The origin of the existence of
groups subordinate to groups, is the same with varieties as with species,
namely, closeness of descent with various degrees of modification. Nearly
the same rules are followed in classifying varieties, as with species.
Authors have insisted on the necessity of classing varieties on a natural
instead of an artificial system; we are cautioned, for instance, not to
class two varieties of the pine-apple together, merely because their fruit,
though the most important part, happens to be nearly identical; no one puts
the swedish and common turnips together, though the esculent and thickened
stems are so similar. Whatever part is found to be most constant, is used
in classing varieties: thus the great agriculturist Marshall says the
horns are very useful for this purpose with cattle, because they are less
variable than the shape or colour of the body, &c.; whereas with sheep the
horns are much less serviceable, because less constant. In classing
varieties, I apprehend if we had a real pedigree, a genealogical
classification would be universally preferred; and it has been attempted by
some authors. For we might feel sure, whether there had been more or less
modification, the principle of inheritance would keep the forms together
which were allied in the greatest number of points. In tumbler pigeons,
though some sub-varieties differ from the others in the important character
of having a longer beak, yet all are kept together from having the common
habit of tumbling; but the short-faced breed has nearly or quite lost this
habit; nevertheless, without any reasoning or thinking on the subject,
these tumblers are kept in the same group, because allied in blood and
alike in some other respects. If it could be proved that the Hottentot had
descended from the Negro, I think he would be classed under the Negro
group, however much he might differ in colour and other important
characters from negroes.
With species in a state of nature, every naturalist has in fact brought
descent into his classification; for he includes in his lowest grade, or
that of a species, the two sexes; and how enormously these sometimes differ
in the most important characters, is known to every naturalist: scarcely a
single fact can be predicated in common of the males and hermaphrodites of
certain cirripedes, when adult, and yet no one dreams of separating them.
The naturalist includes as one species the several larval stages of the
same individual, however much they may differ from each other and from the
adult; as he likewise includes the so-called alternate generations of
Steenstrup, which can only in a technical sense be considered as the same
individual. He includes monsters; he includes varieties, not solely
because they closely resemble the parent-form, but because they are
descended from it. He who believes that the cowslip is descended from the
primrose, or conversely, ranks them together as a single species, and gives
a single definition. As soon as three Orchidean forms (Monochanthus,
Myanthus, and Catasetum), which had previously been ranked as three
distinct genera, were known to be sometimes produced on the same spike,
they were immediately included as a single species. But it may be asked,
what ought we to do, if it could be proved that one species of kangaroo had
been produced, by a long course of modification, from a bear? Ought we to
rank this one species with bears, and what should we do with the other
species? The supposition is of course preposterous; and I might answer by
the argumentum ad hominem, and ask what should be done if a perfect
kangaroo were seen to come out of the womb of a bear? According to all
analogy, it would be ranked with bears; but then assuredly all the other
species of the kangaroo family would have to be classed under the bear
genus. The whole case is preposterous; for where there has been close
descent in common, there will certainly be close resemblance or affinity.
As descent has universally been used in classing together the individuals
of the same species, though the males and females and larvae are sometimes
extremely different; and as it has been used in classing varieties which
have undergone a certain, and sometimes a considerable amount of
modification, may not this same element of descent have been unconsciously
used in grouping species under genera, and genera under higher groups,
though in these cases the modification has been greater in degree, and has
taken a longer time to complete? I believe it has thus been unconsciously
used; and only thus can I understand the several rules and guides which
have been followed by our best systematists. We have no written pedigrees;
we have to make out community of descent by resemblances of any kind.
Therefore we choose those characters which, as far as we can judge, are the
least likely to have been modified in relation to the conditions of life to
which each species has been recently exposed. Rudimentary structures on
this view are as good as, or even sometimes better than, other parts of the
organisation. We care not how trifling a character may be--let it be the
mere inflection of the angle of the jaw, the manner in which an insect's
wing is folded, whether the skin be covered by hair or feathers--if it
prevail throughout many and different species, especially those having very
different habits of life, it assumes high value; for we can account for its
presence in so many forms with such different habits, only by its
inheritance from a common parent. We may err in this respect in regard to
single points of structure, but when several characters, let them be ever
so trifling, occur together throughout a large group of beings having
different habits, we may feel almost sure, on the theory of descent, that
these characters have been inherited from a common ancestor. And we know
that such correlated or aggregated characters have especial value in
classification.
We can understand why a species or a group of species may depart, in
several of its most important characteristics, from its allies, and yet be
safely classed with them. This may be safely done, and is often done, as
long as a sufficient number of characters, let them be ever so unimportant,
betrays the hidden bond of community of descent. Let two forms have not a
single character in common, yet if these extreme forms are connected
together by a chain of intermediate groups, we may at once infer their
community of descent, and we put them all into the same class. As we find
organs of high physiological importance--those which serve to preserve life
under the most diverse conditions of existence--are generally the most
constant, we attach especial value to them; but if these same organs, in
another group or section of a group, are found to differ much, we at once
value them less in our classification. We shall hereafter, I think,
clearly see why embryological characters are of such high classificatory
importance. Geographical distribution may sometimes be brought usefully
into play in classing large and widely-distributed genera, because all the
species of the same genus, inhabiting any distinct and isolated region,
have in all probability descended from the same parents.
We can understand, on these views, the very important distinction between
real affinities and analogical or adaptive resemblances. Lamarck first
called attention to this distinction, and he has been ably followed by
Macleay and others. The resemblance, in the shape of the body and in the
fin-like anterior limbs, between the dugong, which is a pachydermatous
animal, and the whale, and between both these mammals and fishes, is
analogical. Amongst insects there are innumerable instances: thus
Linnaeus, misled by external appearances, actually classed an homopterous
insect as a moth. We see something of the same kind even in our domestic
varieties, as in the thickened stems of the common and swedish turnip. The
resemblance of the greyhound and racehorse is hardly more fanciful than the
analogies which have been drawn by some authors between very distinct
animals. On my view of characters being of real importance for
classification, only in so far as they reveal descent, we can clearly
understand why analogical or adaptive character, although of the utmost
importance to the welfare of the being, are almost valueless to the
systematist. For animals, belonging to two most distinct lines of descent,
may readily become adapted to similar conditions, and thus assume a close
external resemblance; but such resemblances will not reveal--will rather
tend to conceal their blood-relationship to their proper lines of descent.
We can also understand the apparent paradox, that the very same characters
are analogical when one class or order is compared with another, but give
true affinities when the members of the same class or order are compared
one with another: thus the shape of the body and fin-like limbs are only
analogical when whales are compared with fishes, being adaptations in both
classes for swimming through the water; but the shape of the body and
fin-like limbs serve as characters exhibiting true affinity between the
several members of the whale family; for these cetaceans agree in so many
characters, great and small, that we cannot doubt that they have inherited
their general shape of body and structure of limbs from a common ancestor.
So it is with fishes.
As members of distinct classes have often been adapted by successive slight
modifications to live under nearly similar circumstances,--to inhabit for
instance the three elements of land, air, and water,--we can perhaps
understand how it is that a numerical parallelism has sometimes been
observed between the sub-groups in distinct classes. A naturalist, struck
by a parallelism of this nature in any one class, by arbitrarily raising or
sinking the value of the groups in other classes (and all our experience
shows that this valuation has hitherto been arbitrary), could easily extend
the parallelism over a wide range; and thus the septenary, quinary,
quaternary, and ternary classifications have probably arisen.
As the modified descendants of dominant species, belonging to the larger
genera, tend to inherit the advantages, which made the groups to which they
belong large and their parents dominant, they are almost sure to spread
widely, and to seize on more and more places in the economy of nature. The
larger and more dominant groups thus tend to go on increasing in size; and
they consequently supplant many smaller and feebler groups. Thus we can
account for the fact that all organisms, recent and extinct, are included
under a few great orders, under still fewer classes, and all in one great
natural system. As showing how few the higher groups are in number, and
how widely spread they are throughout the world, the fact is striking, that
the discovery of Australia has not added a single insect belonging to a new
order; and that in the vegetable kingdom, as I learn from Dr. Hooker, it
has added only two or three orders of small size.
In the chapter on geological succession I attempted to show, on the
principle of each group having generally diverged much in character during
the long-continued process of modification, how it is that the more ancient
forms of life often present characters in some slight degree intermediate
between existing groups. A few old and intermediate parent-forms having
occasionally transmitted to the present day descendants but little
modified, will give to us our so-called osculant or aberrant groups. The
more aberrant any form is, the greater must be the number of connecting
forms which on my theory have been exterminated and utterly lost. And we
have some evidence of aberrant forms having suffered severely from
extinction, for they are generally represented by extremely few species;
and such species as do occur are generally very distinct from each other,
which again implies extinction. The genera Ornithorhynchus and
Lepidosiren, for example, would not have been less aberrant had each been
represented by a dozen species instead of by a single one; but such
richness in species, as I find after some investigation, does not commonly
fall to the lot of aberrant genera. We can, I think, account for this fact
only by looking at aberrant forms as failing groups conquered by more
successful competitors, with a few members preserved by some unusual
coincidence of favourable circumstances.
Mr. Waterhouse has remarked that, when a member belonging to one group of
animals exhibits an affinity to a quite distinct group, this affinity in
most cases is general and not special: thus, according to Mr. Waterhouse,
of all Rodents, the bizcacha is most nearly related to Marsupials; but in
the points in which it approaches this order, its relations are general,
and not to any one marsupial species more than to another. As the points
of affinity of the bizcacha to Marsupials are believed to be real and not
merely adaptive, they are due on my theory to inheritance in common.
Therefore we must suppose either that all Rodents, including the bizcacha,
branched off from some very ancient Marsupial, which will have had a
character in some degree intermediate with respect to all existing
Marsupials; or that both Rodents and Marsupials branched off from a common
progenitor, and that both groups have since undergone much modification in
divergent directions. On either view we may suppose that the bizcacha has
retained, by inheritance, more of the character of its ancient progenitor
than have other Rodents; and therefore it will not be specially related to
any one existing Marsupial, but indirectly to all or nearly all Marsupials,
from having partially retained the character of their common progenitor, or
of an early member of the group. On the other hand, of all Marsupials, as
Mr. Waterhouse has remarked, the phascolomys resembles most nearly, not any
one species, but the general order of Rodents. In this case, however, it
may be strongly suspected that the resemblance is only analogical, owing to
the phascolomys having become adapted to habits like those of a Rodent.
The elder De Candolle has made nearly similar observations on the general
nature of the affinities of distinct orders of plants.
On the principle of the multiplication and gradual divergence in character
of the species descended from a common parent, together with their
retention by inheritance of some characters in common, we can understand
the excessively complex and radiating affinities by which all the members
of the same family or higher group are connected together. For the common
parent of a whole family of species, now broken up by extinction into
distinct groups and sub-groups, will have transmitted some of its
characters, modified in various ways and degrees, to all; and the several
species will consequently be related to each other by circuitous lines of
affinity of various lengths (as may be seen in the diagram so often
referred to), mounting up through many predecessors. As it is difficult to
show the blood-relationship between the numerous kindred of any ancient and
noble family, even by the aid of a genealogical tree, and almost impossible
to do this without this aid, we can understand the extraordinary difficulty
which naturalists have experienced in describing, without the aid of a
diagram, the various affinities which they perceive between the many living
and extinct members of the same great natural class.
Extinction, as we have seen in the fourth chapter, has played an important
part in defining and widening the intervals between the several groups in
each class. We may thus account even for the distinctness of whole classes
from each other--for instance, of birds from all other vertebrate
animals--by the belief that many ancient forms of life have been utterly
lost, through which the early progenitors of birds were formerly connected
with the early progenitors of the other vertebrate classes. There has been
less entire extinction of the forms of life which once connected fishes
with batrachians. There has been still less in some other classes, as in
that of the Crustacea, for here the most wonderfully diverse forms are
still tied together by a long, but broken, chain of affinities. Extinction
has only separated groups: it has by no means made them; for if every form
which has ever lived on this earth were suddenly to reappear, though it
would be quite impossible to give definitions by which each group could be
distinguished from other groups, as all would blend together by steps as
fine as those between the finest existing varieties, nevertheless a natural
classification, or at least a natural arrangement, would be possible. We
shall see this by turning to the diagram: the letters, A to L, may
represent eleven Silurian genera, some of which have produced large groups
of modified descendants. Every intermediate link between these eleven
genera and their primordial parent, and every intermediate link in each
branch and sub-branch of their descendants, may be supposed to be still
alive; and the links to be as fine as those between the finest varieties.
In this case it would be quite impossible to give any definition by which
the several members of the several groups could be distinguished from their
more immediate parents; or these parents from their ancient and unknown
progenitor. Yet the natural arrangement in the diagram would still hold
good; and, on the principle of inheritance, all the forms descended from A,
or from I, would have something in common. In a tree we can specify this
or that branch, though at the actual fork the two unite and blend together.
We could not, as I have said, define the several groups; but we could pick
out types, or forms, representing most of the characters of each group,
whether large or small, and thus give a general idea of the value of the
differences between them. This is what we should be driven to, if we were
ever to succeed in collecting all the forms in any class which have lived
throughout all time and space. We shall certainly never succeed in making
so perfect a collection: nevertheless, in certain classes, we are tending
in this direction; and Milne Edwards has lately insisted, in an able paper,
on the high importance of looking to types, whether or not we can separate
and define the groups to which such types belong.
Finally, we have seen that natural selection, which results from the
struggle for existence, and which almost inevitably induces extinction and
divergence of character in the many descendants from one dominant
parent-species, explains that great and universal feature in the affinities
of all organic beings, namely, their subordination in group under group.
We use the element of descent in classing the individuals of both sexes and
of all ages, although having few characters in common, under one species;
we use descent in classing acknowledged varieties, however different they
may be from their parent; and I believe this element of descent is the
hidden bond of connexion which naturalists have sought under the term of
the Natural System. On this idea of the natural system being, in so far as
it has been perfected, genealogical in its arrangement, with the grades of
difference between the descendants from a common parent, expressed by the
terms genera, families, orders, &c., we can understand the rules which we
are compelled to follow in our classification. We can understand why we
value certain resemblances far more than others; why we are permitted to
use rudimentary and useless organs, or others of trifling physiological
importance; why, in comparing one group with a distinct group, we summarily
reject analogical or adaptive characters, and yet use these same characters
within the limits of the same group. We can clearly see how it is that all
living and extinct forms can be grouped together in one great system; and
how the several members of each class are connected together by the most
complex and radiating lines of affinities. We shall never, probably,
disentangle the inextricable web of affinities between the members of any
one class; but when we have a distinct object in view, and do not look to
some unknown plan of creation, we may hope to make sure but slow progress.
Morphology. -- We have seen that the members of the same class,
independently of their habits of life, resemble each other in the general
plan of their organisation. This resemblance is often expressed by the
term 'unity of type;' or by saying that the several parts and organs in the
different species of the class are homologous. The whole subject is
included under the general name of Morphology. This is the most
interesting department of natural history, and may be said to be its very
soul. What can be more curious than that the hand of a man, formed for
grasping, that of a mole for digging, the leg of the horse, the paddle of
the porpoise, and the wing of the bat, should all be constructed on the
same pattern, and should include the same bones, in the same relative
positions? Geoffroy St. Hilaire has insisted strongly on the high
importance of relative connexion in homologous organs: the parts may
change to almost any extent in form and size, and yet they always remain
connected together in the same order. We never find, for instance, the
bones of the arm and forearm, or of the thigh and leg, transposed. Hence
the same names can be given to the homologous bones in widely different
animals. We see the same great law in the construction of the mouths of
insects: what can be more different than the immensely long spiral
proboscis of a sphinx-moth, the curious folded one of a bee or bug, and the
great jaws of a beetle?--yet all these organs, serving for such different
purposes, are formed by infinitely numerous modifications of an upper lip,
mandibles, and two pairs of maxillae. Analogous laws govern the
construction of the mouths and limbs of crustaceans. So it is with the
flowers of plants.
Nothing can be more hopeless than to attempt to explain this similarity of
pattern in members of the same class, by utility or by the doctrine of
final causes. The hopelessness of the attempt has been expressly admitted
by Owen in his most interesting work on the 'Nature of Limbs.' On the
ordinary view of the independent creation of each being, we can only say
that so it is;--that it has so pleased the Creator to construct each animal
and plant.
The explanation is manifest on the theory of the natural selection of
successive slight modifications,--each modification being profitable in
some way to the modified form, but often affecting by correlation of growth
other parts of the organisation. In changes of this nature, there will be
little or no tendency to modify the original pattern, or to transpose
parts. The bones of a limb might be shortened and widened to any extent,
and become gradually enveloped in thick membrane, so as to serve as a fin;
or a webbed foot might have all its bones, or certain bones, lengthened to
any extent, and the membrane connecting them increased to any extent, so as
to serve as a wing: yet in all this great amount of modification there
will be no tendency to alter the framework of bones or the relative
connexion of the several parts. If we suppose that the ancient progenitor,
the archetype as it may be called, of all mammals, had its limbs
constructed on the existing general pattern, for whatever purpose they
served, we can at once perceive the plain signification of the homologous
construction of the limbs throughout the whole class. So with the mouths
of insects, we have only to suppose that their common progenitor had an
upper lip, mandibles, and two pair of maxillae, these parts being perhaps
very simple in form; and then natural selection will account for the
infinite diversity in structure and function of the mouths of insects.
Nevertheless, it is conceivable that the general pattern of an organ might
become so much obscured as to be finally lost, by the atrophy and
ultimately by the complete abortion of certain parts, by the soldering
together of other parts, and by the doubling or multiplication of
others,--variations which we know to be within the limits of possibility.
In the paddles of the extinct gigantic sea-lizards, and in the mouths of
certain suctorial crustaceans, the general pattern seems to have been thus
to a certain extent obscured.
There is another and equally curious branch of the present subject; namely,
the comparison not of the same part in different members of a class, but of
the different parts or organs in the same individual. Most physiologists
believe that the bones of the skull are homologous with--that is correspond
in number and in relative connexion with--the elemental parts of a certain
number of vertebrae. The anterior and posterior limbs in each member of
the vertebrate and articulate classes are plainly homologous. We see the
same law in comparing the wonderfully complex jaws and legs in crustaceans.
It is familiar to almost every one, that in a flower the relative position
of the sepals, petals, stamens, and pistils, as well as their intimate
structure, are intelligible on the view that they consist of metamorphosed
leaves, arranged in a spire. In monstrous plants, we often get direct
evidence of the possibility of one organ being transformed into another;
and we can actually see in embryonic crustaceans and in many other animals,
and in flowers, that organs, which when mature become extremely different,
are at an early stage of growth exactly alike.
How inexplicable are these facts on the ordinary view of creation! Why
should the brain be enclosed in a box composed of such numerous and such
extraordinarily shaped pieces of bone? As Owen has remarked, the benefit
derived from the yielding of the separate pieces in the act of parturition
of mammals, will by no means explain the same construction in the skulls of
birds. Why should similar bones have been created in the formation of the
wing and leg of a bat, used as they are for such totally different
purposes? Why should one crustacean, which has an extremely complex mouth
formed of many parts, consequently always have fewer legs; or conversely,
those with many legs have simpler mouths? Why should the sepals, petals,
stamens, and pistils in any individual flower, though fitted for such
widely different purposes, be all constructed on the same pattern?
On the theory of natural selection, we can satisfactorily answer these
questions. In the vertebrata, we see a series of internal vertebrae
bearing certain processes and appendages; in the articulata, we see the
body divided into a series of segments, bearing external appendages; and in
flowering plants, we see a series of successive spiral whorls of leaves.
An indefinite repetition of the same part or organ is the common
characteristic (as Owen has observed) of all low or little-modified forms;
therefore we may readily believe that the unknown progenitor of the
vertebrata possessed many vertebrae; the unknown progenitor of the
articulata, many segments; and the unknown progenitor of flowering plants,
many spiral whorls of leaves. We have formerly seen that parts many times
repeated are eminently liable to vary in number and structure; consequently
it is quite probable that natural selection, during a long-continued course
of modification, should have seized on a certain number of the primordially
similar elements, many times repeated, and have adapted them to the most
diverse purposes. And as the whole amount of modification will have been
effected by slight successive steps, we need not wonder at discovering in
such parts or organs, a certain degree of fundamental resemblance, retained
by the strong principle of inheritance.
In the great class of molluscs, though we can homologise the parts of one
species with those of another and distinct species, we can indicate but few
serial homologies; that is, we are seldom enabled to say that one part or
organ is homologous with another in the same individual. And we can
understand this fact; for in molluscs, even in the lowest members of the
class, we do not find nearly so much indefinite repetition of any one part,
as we find in the other great classes of the animal and vegetable kingdoms.
Naturalists frequently speak of the skull as formed of metamorphosed
vertebrae: the jaws of crabs as metamorphosed legs; the stamens and
pistils of flowers as metamorphosed leaves; but it would in these cases
probably be more correct, as Professor Huxley has remarked, to speak of
both skull and vertebrae, both jaws and legs, &c.,--as having been
metamorphosed, not one from the other, but from some common element.
Naturalists, however, use such language only in a metaphorical sense: they
are far from meaning that during a long course of descent, primordial
organs of any kind--vertebrae in the one case and legs in the other--have
actually been modified into skulls or jaws. Yet so strong is the
appearance of a modification of this nature having occurred, that
naturalists can hardly avoid employing language having this plain
signification. On my view these terms may be used literally; and the
wonderful fact of the jaws, for instance, of a crab retaining numerous
characters, which they would probably have retained through inheritance, if
they had really been metamorphosed during a long course of descent from
true legs, or from some simple appendage, is explained.
Embryology. -- It has already been casually remarked that certain organs in
the individual, which when mature become widely different and serve for
different purposes, are in the embryo exactly alike. The embryos, also, of
distinct animals within the same class are often strikingly similar: a
better proof of this cannot be given, than a circumstance mentioned by
Agassiz, namely, that having forgotten to ticket the embryo of some
vertebrate animal, he cannot now tell whether it be that of a mammal, bird,
or reptile. The vermiform larvae of moths, flies, beetles, &c., resemble
each other much more closely than do the mature insects; but in the case of
larvae, the embryos are active, and have been adapted for special lines of
life. A trace of the law of embryonic resemblance, sometimes lasts till a
rather late age: thus birds of the same genus, and of closely allied
genera, often resemble each other in their first and second plumage; as we
see in the spotted feathers in the thrush group. In the cat tribe, most of
the species are striped or spotted in lines; and stripes can be plainly
distinguished in the whelp of the lion. We occasionally though rarely see
something of this kind in plants: thus the embryonic leaves of the ulex or
furze, and the first leaves of the phyllodineous acaceas, are pinnate or
divided like the ordinary leaves of the leguminosae.
The points of structure, in which the embryos of widely different animals
of the same class resemble each other, often have no direct relation to
their conditions of existence. We cannot, for instance, suppose that in
the embryos of the vertebrata the peculiar loop-like course of the arteries
near the branchial slits are related to similar conditions,--in the young
mammal which is nourished in the womb of its mother, in the egg of the bird
which is hatched in a nest, and in the spawn of a frog under water. We
have no more reason to believe in such a relation, than we have to believe
that the same bones in the hand of a man, wing of a bat, and fin of a
porpoise, are related to similar conditions of life. No one will suppose
that the stripes on the whelp of a lion, or the spots on the young
blackbird, are of any use to these animals, or are related to the
conditions to which they are exposed.
The case, however, is different when an animal during any part of its
embryonic career is active, and has to provide for itself. The period of
activity may come on earlier or later in life; but whenever it comes on,
the adaptation of the larva to its conditions of life is just as perfect
and as beautiful as in the adult animal. From such special adaptations,
the similarity of the larvae or active embryos of allied animals is
sometimes much obscured; and cases could be given of the larvae of two
species, or of two groups of species, differing quite as much, or even
more, from each other than do their adult parents. In most cases, however,
the larvae, though active, still obey more or less closely the law of
common embryonic resemblance. Cirripedes afford a good instance of this:
even the illustrious Cuvier did not perceive that a barnacle was, as it
certainly is, a crustacean; but a glance at the larva shows this to be the
case in an unmistakeable manner. So again the two main divisions of
cirripedes, the pedunculated and sessile, which differ widely in external
appearance, have larvae in all their several stages barely distinguishable.
The embryo in the course of development generally rises in organisation: I
use this expression, though I am aware that it is hardly possible to define
clearly what is meant by the organisation being higher or lower. But no
one probably will dispute that the butterfly is higher than the
caterpillar. In some cases, however, the mature animal is generally
considered as lower in the scale than the larva, as with certain parasitic
crustaceans. To refer once again to cirripedes: the larvae in the first
stage have three pairs of legs, a very simple single eye, and a
probosciformed mouth, with which they feed largely, for they increase much
in size. In the second stage, answering to the chrysalis stage of
butterflies, they have six pairs of beautifully constructed natatory legs,
a pair of magnificent compound eyes, and extremely complex antennae; but
they have a closed and imperfect mouth, and cannot feed: their function at
this stage is, to search by their well-developed organs of sense, and to
reach by their active powers of swimming, a proper place on which to become
attached and to undergo their final metamorphosis. When this is completed
they are fixed for life: their legs are now converted into prehensile
organs; they again obtain a well-constructed mouth; but they have no
antennae, and their two eyes are now reconverted into a minute, single, and
very simple eye-spot. In this last and complete state, cirripedes may be
considered as either more highly or more lowly organised than they were in
the larval condition. But in some genera the larvae become developed
either into hermaphrodites having the ordinary structure, or into what I
have called complemental males: and in the latter, the development has
assuredly been retrograde; for the male is a mere sack, which lives for a
short time, and is destitute of mouth, stomach, or other organ of
importance, excepting for reproduction.
We are so much accustomed to see differences in structure between the
embryo and the adult, and likewise a close similarity in the embryos of
widely different animals within the same class, that we might be led to
look at these facts as necessarily contingent in some manner on growth.
But there is no obvious reason why, for instance, the wing of a bat, or the
fin of a porpoise, should not have been sketched out with all the parts in
proper proportion, as soon as any structure became visible in the embryo.
And in some whole groups of animals and in certain members of other groups,
the embryo does not at any period differ widely from the adult: thus Owen
has remarked in regard to cuttle-fish, 'there is no metamorphosis; the
cephalopodic character is manifested long before the parts of the embryo
are completed;' and again in spiders, 'there is nothing worthy to be called
a metamorphosis.' The larvae of insects, whether adapted to the most
diverse and active habits, or quite inactive, being fed by their parents or
placed in the midst of proper nutriment, yet nearly all pass through a
similar worm-like stage of development; but in some few cases, as in that
of Aphis, if we look to the admirable drawings by Professor Huxley of the
development of this insect, we see no trace of the vermiform stage.
How, then, can we explain these several facts in embryology,--namely the
very general, but not universal difference in structure between the embryo
and the adult;--of parts in the same individual embryo, which ultimately
become very unlike and serve for diverse purposes, being at this early
period of growth alike;--of embryos of different species within the same
class, generally, but not universally, resembling each other;--of the
structure of the embryo not being closely related to its conditions of
existence, except when the embryo becomes at any period of life active and
has to provide for itself;--of the embryo apparently having sometimes a
higher organisation than the mature animal, into which it is developed. I
believe that all these facts can be explained, as follows, on the view of
descent with modification.
It is commonly assumed, perhaps from monstrosities often affecting the
embryo at a very early period, that slight variations necessarily appear at
an equally early period. But we have little evidence on this head--indeed
the evidence rather points the other way; for it is notorious that breeders
of cattle, horses, and various fancy animals, cannot positively tell, until
some time after the animal has been born, what its merits or form will
ultimately turn out. We see this plainly in our own children; we cannot
always tell whether the child will be tall or short, or what its precise
features will be. The question is not, at what period of life any
variation has been caused, but at what period it is fully displayed. The
cause may have acted, and I believe generally has acted, even before the
embryo is formed; and the variation may be due to the male and female
sexual elements having been affected by the conditions to which either
parent, or their ancestors, have been exposed. Nevertheless an effect thus
caused at a very early period, even before the formation of the embryo, may
appear late in life; as when an hereditary disease, which appears in old
age alone, has been communicated to the offspring from the reproductive
element of one parent. Or again, as when the horns of cross-bred cattle
have been affected by the shape of the horns of either parent. For the
welfare of a very young animal, as long as it remains in its mother's womb,
or in the egg, or as long as it is nourished and protected by its parent,
it must be quite unimportant whether most of its characters are fully
acquired a little earlier or later in life. It would not signify, for
instance, to a bird which obtained its food best by having a long beak,
whether or not it assumed a beak of this particular length, as long as it
was fed by its parents. Hence, I conclude, that it is quite possible, that
each of the many successive modifications, by which each species has
acquired its present structure, may have supervened at a not very early
period of life; and some direct evidence from our domestic animals supports
this view. But in other cases it is quite possible that each successive
modification, or most of them, may have appeared at an extremely early
period.
I have stated in the first chapter, that there is some evidence to render
it probable, that at whatever age any variation first appears in the
parent, it tends to reappear at a corresponding age in the offspring.
Certain variations can only appear at corresponding ages, for instance,
peculiarities in the caterpillar, cocoon, or imago states of the silk-moth;
or, again, in the horns of almost full-grown cattle. But further than
this, variations which, for all that we can see, might have appeared
earlier or later in life, tend to appear at a corresponding age in the
offspring and parent. I am far from meaning that this is invariably the
case; and I could give a good many cases of variations (taking the word in
the largest sense) which have supervened at an earlier age in the child
than in the parent.
These two principles, if their truth be admitted, will, I believe, explain
all the above specified leading facts in embryology. But first let us look
at a few analogous cases in domestic varieties. Some authors who have
written on Dogs, maintain that the greyhound and bulldog, though appearing
so different, are really varieties most closely allied, and have probably
descended from the same wild stock; hence I was curious to see how far
their puppies differed from each other: I was told by breeders that they
differed just as much as their parents, and this, judging by the eye,
seemed almost to be the case; but on actually measuring the old dogs and
their six-days old puppies, I found that the puppies had not nearly
acquired their full amount of proportional difference. So, again, I was
told that the foals of cart and race-horses differed as much as the
full-grown animals; and this surprised me greatly, as I think it probable
that the difference between these two breeds has been wholly caused by
selection under domestication; but having had careful measurements made of
the dam and of a three-days old colt of a race and heavy cart-horse, I find
that the colts have by no means acquired their full amount of proportional
difference.
As the evidence appears to me conclusive, that the several domestic breeds
of Pigeon have descended from one wild species, I compared young pigeons of
various breeds, within twelve hours after being hatched; I carefully
measured the proportions (but will not here give details) of the beak,
width of mouth, length of nostril and of eyelid, size of feet and length of
leg, in the wild stock, in pouters, fantails, runts, barbs, dragons,
carriers, and tumblers. Now some of these birds, when mature, differ so
extraordinarily in length and form of beak, that they would, I cannot
doubt, be ranked in distinct genera, had they been natural productions.
But when the nestling birds of these several breeds were placed in a row,
though most of them could be distinguished from each other, yet their
proportional differences in the above specified several points were
incomparably less than in the full-grown birds. Some characteristic points
of difference--for instance, that of the width of mouth--could hardly be
detected in the young. But there was one remarkable exception to this
rule, for the young of the short-faced tumbler differed from the young of
the wild rock-pigeon and of the other breeds, in all its proportions,
almost exactly as much as in the adult state.
The two principles above given seem to me to explain these facts in regard
to the later embryonic stages of our domestic varieties. Fanciers select
their horses, dogs, and pigeons, for breeding, when they are nearly grown
up: they are indifferent whether the desired qualities and structures have
been acquired earlier or later in life, if the full-grown animal possesses
them. And the cases just given, more especially that of pigeons, seem to
show that the characteristic differences which give value to each breed,
and which have been accumulated by man's selection, have not generally
first appeared at an early period of life, and have been inherited by the
offspring at a corresponding not early period. But the case of the
short-faced tumbler, which when twelve hours old had acquired its proper
proportions, proves that this is not the universal rule; for here the
characteristic differences must either have appeared at an earlier period
than usual, or, if not so, the differences must have been inherited, not at
the corresponding, but at an earlier age.
Now let us apply these facts and the above two principles--which latter,
though not proved true, can be shown to be in some degree probable--to
species in a state of nature. Let us take a genus of birds, descended on
my theory from some one parent-species, and of which the several new
species have become modified through natural selection in accordance with
their diverse habits. Then, from the many slight successive steps of
variation having supervened at a rather late age, and having been inherited
at a corresponding age, the young of the new species of our supposed genus
will manifestly tend to resemble each other much more closely than do the
adults, just as we have seen in the case of pigeons. We may extend this
view to whole families or even classes. The fore-limbs, for instance,
which served as legs in the parent-species, may become, by a long course of
modification, adapted in one descendant to act as hands, in another as
paddles, in another as wings; and on the above two principles--namely of
each successive modification supervening at a rather late age, and being
inherited at a corresponding late age--the fore-limbs in the embryos of the
several descendants of the parent-species will still resemble each other
closely, for they will not have been modified. But in each individual new
species, the embryonic fore-limbs will differ greatly from the fore-limbs
in the mature animal; the limbs in the latter having undergone much
modification at a rather late period of life, and having thus been
converted into hands, or paddles, or wings. Whatever influence
long-continued exercise or use on the one hand, and disuse on the other,
may have in modifying an organ, such influence will mainly affect the
mature animal, which has come to its full powers of activity and has to
gain its own living; and the effects thus produced will be inherited at a
corresponding mature age. Whereas the young will remain unmodified, or be
modified in a lesser degree, by the effects of use and disuse.
In certain cases the successive steps of variation might supervene, from
causes of which we are wholly ignorant, at a very early period of life, or
each step might be inherited at an earlier period than that at which it
first appeared. In either case (as with the short-faced tumbler) the young
or embryo would closely resemble the mature parent-form. We have seen that
this is the rule of development in certain whole groups of animals, as with
cuttle-fish and spiders, and with a few members of the great class of
insects, as with Aphis. With respect to the final cause of the young in
these cases not undergoing any metamorphosis, or closely resembling their
parents from their earliest age, we can see that this would result from the
two following contingencies; firstly, from the young, during a course of
modification carried on for many generations, having to provide for their
own wants at a very early stage of development, and secondly, from their
following exactly the same habits of life with their parents; for in this
case, it would be indispensable for the existence of the species, that the
child should be modified at a very early age in the same manner with its
parents, in accordance with their similar habits. Some further
explanation, however, of the embryo not undergoing any metamorphosis is
perhaps requisite. If, on the other hand, it profited the young to follow
habits of life in any degree different from those of their parent, and
consequently to be constructed in a slightly different manner, then, on the
principle of inheritance at corresponding ages, the active young or larvae
might easily be rendered by natural selection different to any conceivable
extent from their parents. Such differences might, also, become correlated
with successive stages of development; so that the larvae, in the first
stage, might differ greatly from the larvae in the second stage, as we have
seen to be the case with cirripedes. The adult might become fitted for
sites or habits, in which organs of locomotion or of the senses, &c., would
be useless; and in this case the final metamorphosis would be said to be
retrograde.
As all the organic beings, extinct and recent, which have ever lived on
this earth have to be classed together, and as all have been connected by
the finest gradations, the best, or indeed, if our collections were nearly
perfect, the only possible arrangement, would be genealogical. Descent
being on my view the hidden bond of connexion which naturalists have been
seeking under the term of the natural system. On this view we can
understand how it is that, in the eyes of most naturalists, the structure
of the embryo is even more important for classification than that of the
adult. For the embryo is the animal in its less modified state; and in so
far it reveals the structure of its progenitor. In two groups of animal,
however much they may at present differ from each other in structure and
habits, if they pass through the same or similar embryonic stages, we may
feel assured that they have both descended from the same or nearly similar
parents, and are therefore in that degree closely related. Thus, community
in embryonic structure reveals community of descent. It will reveal this
community of descent, however much the structure of the adult may have been
modified and obscured; we have seen, for instance, that cirripedes can at
once be recognised by their larvae as belonging to the great class of
crustaceans. As the embryonic state of each species and group of species
partially shows us the structure of their less modified ancient
progenitors, we can clearly see why ancient and extinct forms of life
should resemble the embryos of their descendants,--our existing species.
Agassiz believes this to be a law of nature; but I am bound to confess that
I only hope to see the law hereafter proved true. It can be proved true in
those cases alone in which the ancient state, now supposed to be
represented in many embryos, has not been obliterated, either by the
successive variations in a long course of modification having supervened at
a very early age, or by the variations having been inherited at an earlier
period than that at which they first appeared. It should also be borne in
mind, that the supposed law of resemblance of ancient forms of life to the
embryonic stages of recent forms, may be true, but yet, owing to the
geological record not extending far enough back in time, may remain for a
long period, or for ever, incapable of demonstration.
Thus, as it seems to me, the leading facts in embryology, which are second
in importance to none in natural history, are explained on the principle of
slight modifications not appearing, in the many descendants from some one
ancient progenitor, at a very early period in the life of each, though
perhaps caused at the earliest, and being inherited at a corresponding not
early period. Embryology rises greatly in interest, when we thus look at
the embryo as a picture, more or less obscured, of the common parent-form
of each great class of animals.
Rudimentary, atrophied, or aborted organs. -- Organs or parts in this
strange condition, bearing the stamp of inutility, are extremely common
throughout nature. For instance, rudimentary mammae are very general in
the males of mammals: I presume that the 'bastard-wing' in birds may be
safely considered as a digit in a rudimentary state: in very many snakes
one lobe of the lungs is rudimentary; in other snakes there are rudiments
of the pelvis and hind limbs. Some of the cases of rudimentary organs are
extremely curious; for instance, the presence of teeth in foetal whales,
which when grown up have not a tooth in their heads; and the presence of
teeth, which never cut through the gums, in the upper jaws of our unborn
calves. It has even been stated on good authority that rudiments of teeth
can be detected in the beaks of certain embryonic birds. Nothing can be
plainer than that wings are formed for flight, yet in how many insects do
we see wings so reduced in size as to be utterly incapable of flight, and
not rarely lying under wing-cases, firmly soldered together!
The meaning of rudimentary organs is often quite unmistakeable: for
instance there are beetles of the same genus (and even of the same species)
resembling each other most closely in all respects, one of which will have
full-sized wings, and another mere rudiments of membrane; and here it is
impossible to doubt, that the rudiments represent wings. Rudimentary
organs sometimes retain their potentiality, and are merely not developed:
this seems to be the case with the mammae of male mammals, for many
instances are on record of these organs having become well developed in
full-grown males, and having secreted milk. So again there are normally
four developed and two rudimentary teats in the udders of the genus Bos,
but in our domestic cows the two sometimes become developed and give milk.
In individual plants of the same species the petals sometimes occur as mere
rudiments, and sometimes in a well-developed state. In plants with
separated sexes, the male flowers often have a rudiment of a pistil; and
Kolreuter found that by crossing such male plants with an hermaphrodite
species, the rudiment of the pistil in the hybrid offspring was much
increased in size; and this shows that the rudiment and the perfect pistil
are essentially alike in nature.
An organ serving for two purposes, may become rudimentary or utterly
aborted for one, even the more important purpose; and remain perfectly
efficient for the other. Thus in plants, the office of the pistil is to
allow the pollen-tubes to reach the ovules protected in the ovarium at its
base. The pistil consists of a stigma supported on the style; but in some
Compositae, the male florets, which of course cannot be fecundated, have a
pistil, which is in a rudimentary state, for it is not crowned with a
stigma; but the style remains well developed, and is clothed with hairs as
in other compositae, for the purpose of brushing the pollen out of the
surrounding anthers. Again, an organ may become rudimentary for its proper
purpose, and be used for a distinct object: in certain fish the
swim-bladder seems to be rudimentary for its proper function of giving
buoyancy, but has become converted into a nascent breathing organ or lung.
Other similar instances could be given.
Rudimentary organs in the individuals of the same species are very liable
to vary in degree of development and in other respects. Moreover, in
closely allied species, the degree to which the same organ has been
rendered rudimentary occasionally differs much. This latter fact is well
exemplified in the state of the wings of the female moths in certain
groups. Rudimentary organs may be utterly aborted; and this implies, that
we find in an animal or plant no trace of an organ, which analogy would
lead us to expect to find, and which is occasionally found in monstrous
individuals of the species. Thus in the snapdragon (antirrhinum) we
generally do not find a rudiment of a fifth stamen; but this may sometimes
be seen. In tracing the homologies of the same part in different members
of a class, nothing is more common, or more necessary, than the use and
discovery of rudiments. This is well shown in the drawings given by Owen
of the bones of the leg of the horse, ox, and rhinoceros.
It is an important fact that rudimentary organs, such as teeth in the upper
jaws of whales and ruminants, can often be detected in the embryo, but
afterwards wholly disappear. It is also, I believe, a universal rule, that
a rudimentary part or organ is of greater size relatively to the adjoining
parts in the embryo, than in the adult; so that the organ at this early age
is less rudimentary, or even cannot be said to be in any degree
rudimentary. Hence, also, a rudimentary organ in the adult, is often said
to have retained its embryonic condition.
I have now given the leading facts with respect to rudimentary organs. In
reflecting on them, every one must be struck with astonishment: for the
same reasoning power which tells us plainly that most parts and organs are
exquisitely adapted for certain purposes, tells us with equal plainness
that these rudimentary or atrophied organs, are imperfect and useless. In
works on natural history rudimentary organs are generally said to have been
created 'for the sake of symmetry,' or in order 'to complete the scheme of
nature;' but this seems to me no explanation, merely a restatement of the
fact. Would it be thought sufficient to say that because planets revolve
in elliptic courses round the sun, satellites follow the same course round
the planets, for the sake of symmetry, and to complete the scheme of
nature? An eminent physiologist accounts for the presence of rudimentary
organs, by supposing that they serve to excrete matter in excess, or
injurious to the system; but can we suppose that the minute papilla, which
often represents the pistil in male flowers, and which is formed merely of
cellular tissue, can thus act? Can we suppose that the formation of
rudimentary teeth which are subsequently absorbed, can be of any service to
the rapidly growing embryonic calf by the excretion of precious phosphate
of lime? When a man's fingers have been amputated, imperfect nails
sometimes appear on the stumps: I could as soon believe that these
vestiges of nails have appeared, not from unknown laws of growth, but in
order to excrete horny matter, as that the rudimentary nails on the fin of
the manatee were formed for this purpose.
On my view of descent with modification, the origin of rudimentary organs
is simple. We have plenty of cases of rudimentary organs in our domestic
productions,--as the stump of a tail in tailless breeds,--the vestige of an
ear in earless breeds,--the reappearance of minute dangling horns in
hornless breeds of cattle, more especially, according to Youatt, in young
animals,--and the state of the whole flower in the cauliflower. We often
see rudiments of various parts in monsters. But I doubt whether any of
these cases throw light on the origin of rudimentary organs in a state of
nature, further than by showing that rudiments can be produced; for I doubt
whether species under nature ever undergo abrupt changes. I believe that
disuse has been the main agency; that it has led in successive generations
to the gradual reduction of various organs, until they have become
rudimentary,--as in the case of the eyes of animals inhabiting dark
caverns, and of the wings of birds inhabiting oceanic islands, which have
seldom been forced to take flight, and have ultimately lost the power of
flying. Again, an organ useful under certain conditions, might become
injurious under others, as with the wings of beetles living on small and
exposed islands; and in this case natural selection would continue slowly
to reduce the organ, until it was rendered harmless and rudimentary.
Any change in function, which can be effected by insensibly small steps, is
within the power of natural selection; so that an organ rendered, during
changed habits of life, useless or injurious for one purpose, might easily
be modified and used for another purpose. Or an organ might be retained
for one alone of its former functions. An organ, when rendered useless,
may well be variable, for its variations cannot be checked by natural
selection. At whatever period of life disuse or selection reduces an
organ, and this will generally be when the being has come to maturity and
to its full powers of action, the principle of inheritance at corresponding
ages will reproduce the organ in its reduced state at the same age, and
consequently will seldom affect or reduce it in the embryo. Thus we can
understand the greater relative size of rudimentary organs in the embryo,
and their lesser relative size in the adult. But if each step of the
process of reduction were to be inherited, not at the corresponding age,
but at an extremely early period of life (as we have good reason to believe
to be possible) the rudimentary part would tend to be wholly lost, and we
should have a case of complete abortion. The principle, also, of economy,
explained in a former chapter, by which the materials forming any part or
structure, if not useful to the possessor, will be saved as far as is
possible, will probably often come into play; and this will tend to cause
the entire obliteration of a rudimentary organ.
As the presence of rudimentary organs is thus due to the tendency in every
part of the organisation, which has long existed, to be inherited--we can
understand, on the genealogical view of classification, how it is that
systematists have found rudimentary parts as useful as, or even sometimes
more useful than, parts of high physiological importance. Rudimentary
organs may be compared with the letters in a word, still retained in the
spelling, but become useless in the pronunciation, but which serve as a
clue in seeking for its derivation. On the view of descent with
modification, we may conclude that the existence of organs in a
rudimentary, imperfect, and useless condition, or quite aborted, far from
presenting a strange difficulty, as they assuredly do on the ordinary
doctrine of creation, might even have been anticipated, and can be
accounted for by the laws of inheritance.
Summary. -- In this chapter I have attempted to show, that the
subordination of group to group in all organisms throughout all time; that
the nature of the relationship, by which all living and extinct beings are
united by complex, radiating, and circuitous lines of affinities into one
grand system; the rules followed and the difficulties encountered by
naturalists in their classifications; the value set upon characters, if
constant and prevalent, whether of high vital importance, or of the most
trifling importance, or, as in rudimentary organs, of no importance; the
wide opposition in value between analogical or adaptive characters, and
characters of true affinity; and other such rules;--all naturally follow on
the view of the common parentage of those forms which are considered by
naturalists as allied, together with their modification through natural
selection, with its contingencies of extinction and divergence of
character. In considering this view of classification, it should be borne
in mind that the element of descent has been universally used in ranking
together the sexes, ages, and acknowledged varieties of the same species,
however different they may be in structure. If we extend the use of this
element of descent,--the only certainly known cause of similarity in
organic beings,--we shall understand what is meant by the natural system:
it is genealogical in its attempted arrangement, with the grades of
acquired difference marked by the terms varieties, species, genera,
families, orders, and classes.
On this same view of descent with modification, all the great facts in
Morphology become intelligible,--whether we look to the same pattern
displayed in the homologous organs, to whatever purpose applied, of the
different species of a class; or to the homologous parts constructed on the
same pattern in each individual animal and plant.
On the principle of successive slight variations, not necessarily or
generally supervening at a very early period of life, and being inherited
at a corresponding period, we can understand the great leading facts in
Embryology; namely, the resemblance in an individual embryo of the
homologous parts, which when matured will become widely different from each
other in structure and function; and the resemblance in different species
of a class of the homologous parts or organs, though fitted in the adult
members for purposes as different as possible. Larvae are active embryos,
which have become specially modified in relation to their habits of life,
through the principle of modifications being inherited at corresponding
ages. On this same principle--and bearing in mind, that when organs are
reduced in size, either from disuse or selection, it will generally be at
that period of life when the being has to provide for its own wants, and
bearing in mind how strong is the principle of inheritance--the occurrence
of rudimentary organs and their final abortion, present to us no
inexplicable difficulties; on the contrary, their presence might have been
even anticipated. The importance of embryological characters and of
rudimentary organs in classification is intelligible, on the view that an
arrangement is only so far natural as it is genealogical.
Finally, the several classes of facts which have been considered in this
chapter, seem to me to proclaim so plainly, that the innumerable species,
genera, and families of organic beings, with which this world is peopled,
have all descended, each within its own class or group, from common
parents, and have all been modified in the course of descent, that I should
without hesitation adopt this view, even if it were unsupported by other
facts or arguments.